_______________________________________________________________
_______________________________________________________________
Report Information from ProQuest
23 October 2014 15:47
_______________________________________________________________
23 October 2014 ProQuestTable of contents
1. The Principle of Best Interests of Students in the Principalship................................................................... 1
23 October 2014 ii ProQuestDocument 1 of 1
The Principle of Best Interests of Students in the Principalship
Author: Walker, Keith; Kutsyuruba, Benjamin; Bishop-Yong, Nicola
ProQuest document link
Abstract (Abstract): Analyses of the data revealed that the notion of the best interests of the student(s) was
broadly conceptualized and defined in three major categories of thought: best interests as core good, best
interests as good pedagogy, and best interests as comprehensive good. Most respondents identified with a
definition of best interests as a core good. The best interests of students were regularly described as the core or
center of decision-making and the heart of educators' work. One respondent noted, "I would ask staff members
to always remember why we teach-to educate students. They are our priority." It was evident that the
respondents mitigated decisions of best interests by placing the students at the heart of decision-making, or as
one respondent articulated, "We need to see to their needs ahead of our own." Prevalently, respondents
defined best interests as the why of their work and why they entered teaching. Respondents identified an ethical
duty and responsibility toward providing students with the best possible care and attention including decisions
on their behalf. This sense of service responsibility prevailed that: "Students are our client and we have a
responsibility to our students" and that an agreed central purpose of education, best interests, should be "to
serve students." Finally, respondents defined best interests as the best outcome or as a positive benefit.
Decision-making in this manner was depicted as those decisions that led to students' development,
advancement, and growth. One comment encapsulates this point: "What the phrase [best interest] means to me
is that decisions are made from the perspective of providing the best possible outcome for that child."
When describing best interests as good pedagogy, principals used concepts and phrases like learning,
achievement, learning environment, and pedagogy. The best-interests principle was described as a means to
an end. In the view of some respondents, the central purpose or paramount reason for education was students'
learning as indicated in the following responses: "Our central purpose is student learning. I prefer to define 'best
interests' in the context of good pedagogy," and "I would explain it by saying that the paramount reason we are
in business is to advance student learning. If the decision advances student learning, then it is in the best
interest of the student." Decisions of best interests were identified by the respondents as those that "supported]
student learning [and] achievement in a safe and caring learning environment" or enabled students to "flourish
in an environment that is safe and productive to learning." In addition, the respondents defined decisions of best
interests as "interests that [led] to growth through learning opportunities" and higher achievement."
The matrix represents the arguments of several theorists on best interests such as [Stephen Smith] (1998),
Capron (1982), Walker (1998a) and [Shapiro, J.P.] and Stefkovich (2002b) along the intersecting dichotomies.
Smith, like the judiciary, was concerned with the child in his critique of best interests per the educational leader.
According to Smith, there may be "no singular right, good, or virtuous pattern for all children," yet there may be
a singularly right response for the single child and what fundamentally determines the measure of help given the
child is the moral agency of "people [who] are in better positions relative to particular children than others" (p.
309). Similarly, Shapiro and Stefkovich and Stefkovich (2006) centered their research on assisting those in
"better positions"-in-school administrators-to make ethical decisions in the best interests of the student. The
underlying assumpFi tion is that if the individual is treated with fairness, justice, and caring, then a strong
message is sent to all students that they will be afforded justice and caring and that they should treat others
similarly ([Stefkovich, J.A.]). However, unlike Smith's assessment, Shapiro and Stefkovich appeared to hold the
position of whose interests, individual or collective, in a balance. Dworkin (1982) identified that the struggle for
balancing the interests of the individual and the communal lies in terms of not only value conflicts, but also time
conflicts. Writing about political representatives, he suggests that they are asked to balance the interests and
23 October 2014 Page 1 of 26 ProQuestdesires of some against those of others and may have to consider the interests of current generations against
the needs or interests of future generations. Once again, the nature of interests is relational.
Full text: Headnote
The best-interests principle is a widely used ethical, legal, and social basis for making policy and decisions
involving children. This article provides an overview of the state of the conversation about the best interests of
students and a recent study of the concept as it was understood and used by school principals. The purpose of
this research was to examine the best-interests principle through an investigation of theory, practice, and
professional praxis and thus to identify the common use and understanding of the best-interests principle in
Canadian in-school administrative practice. We discuss the moral nature of educational leadership through a
multidimensional ethical framework that comprises ethics of justice, care, critique, community, and profession.
Research methodology consisted of a structured survey that included both closed attitudinal and open-ended
questions. The findings revealed a compelling image of the best-interests principle in educational administrative
practice, emphasized the significance of the multi-ethical paradigms in decision-making, and positioned in-
school administrators vis àvis best interests on the matrix at the intersection of two dichotomies: a focus of
interest (individual-student or the communal-students) and a methodology of deciding-(subjective-case by case
or objective-criteria-based).
The best-interests principle is a widely used ethical, legal, and social construct for mediating making policy and
decisions involving children (Kopelman, 1997). As such, the applications of the principle abound in legal,
medical, and educational contexts where determinations are made on behalf of children. The construct
represents the guiding criterion for legal disputes about custody and access (Department of Justice Canada,
2004). In addition, this notion is a common reference point used in quasi-medical and medical contexts (Bailey,
2006; Kopelman). In educational contexts, the best-interests principle has received increased attention in the
mitigation of ethical and legal decision-making (Cranston, Ehrich, &Kimber, 2006; Frick, 2006; Shapiro
&Stefkovich, 2001a; Stefkovich &Begley, 2007; Stefkovich &O'Brien, 2004; Tirri, 1999; Tirri &Husu, 2002;
Walker, 1995,1998a)
The best interests of students has become a common shibboleth of "enormous potential to direct and to
measure goodness, Tightness, and appropriateness of policy and practice" (Walker, 1995, p. 5) for educators,
policymakers, and legal adjudicators. The phrase is a first source of demarcation for educators who will often
evoke the phrase to show their colors. As such, it is the common proxy for saying, "All that we do and say in
education ought to be in the stewardship of our compelling moral purpose to support the healthy growth and
development of children and youth." Often the phrase is used as a shorthand expression of the taken-for-
granted summum bonum (the greatest good) that must be preserved in the outworking of all or any educational
policy decisions; as in "We must not transgress the best interests of the students with this new policy." Also, of
course, in the reading of almost any legal case dealing with the interests of the child or the competing interests
of adults where children are involved, one witnesses the use of the construct of best interests as a hinge
(cardinal) principle against which the warrants of conflicting perspectives must be measured before resolving
decisions may be made. Much best-interests discourse appears inside and around educational organizations
(i.e., staff rooms, classrooms, schools, and school systems), in the work of education policy agents, and in
societal institutions (governments and judicial bodies). However, although the concept is present in the parlance
of educational communities, we argue that there is a lack of meaningful attention and exegesis in proportion to
its evocative use.
Although work has been done to theorize best interests as a guiding principle in ethical leadership and decision-
making in education, only a small number of empirical studies have been conducted, and qualitative research
on the perceptions of this principle by educational leaders has been inconclusive (Frick, 2006; Shapiro
&Stefkovich, 2001a, 2001b; Stefkovich, 2006; Walker, 1995). Despite attempts to provide a rigorous definition,
the research reveals that best interests is used broadly and interpreted in multiple ways. Consequently, the
23 October 2014 Page 2 of 26 ProQuest"potent phrase" (Walker, 1998a), often used as justification and rationalization for administrative decisions,
requires critical examination. Of course, difficult and "wicked" problems do not rely on rational, traditional, or
bureaucratic policy and decision-making processes for resolution, but we would still advocate a view that the
use of in the best interests of the student(s) by school principals requires mapping and charting. It is imperative
for in-school administrators to grapple with the complexities of applying the best-interests principle, both ethical
and jurisprudential. Our effort here is not to simplify the work of school leaders, but to begin to unpack and
make sense of a concept that may be espoused without appreciation of either the substantive construct or the
context complexities. For as Walker (1995) wrote, "the more committed and competent we are in finding the
ethical courage to do what is clearly in the best interests of children, the better we will serve the children of our
schools" (p. 8). Studies on the best-interests principle represent a significant opportunity to examine various
dimensions of ethical leadership. Although the child, children, the student, or the students should not be
essentialized or homogenized, a critical perspective of these central constructs is beyond the scope of this
article.
Here we provide an overview of the state of the conversation about the best interests of students and report on
a recent study that focused on the concept as it was understood and used by school principals. The purpose of
this research was to examine the best-interests principle through an investigation of theory, practice, and
professional praxis, and thus to identify the common use and understandings of the best-interests principle in
Canadian in-school administrative practice. In the following sections, we begin the discussion of the moral
nature of educational leadership through a multidimensional ethical framework comprising ethics of justice,
care, critique, community, and profession, together with jurisprudential and ethical decision-making
perspectives. We then describe and discuss the perceptions of Canadian principals regarding the notion of best
interests of students and ethical dilemmas in administrative decision-making. The article concludes with an
interpretative matrix to describe principals' perspectives and the challenges for ongoing research related to this
persistently important concept.
Ethical Frameworks and Educational Leaders' Pursuit of Students' Best Interests
Although principalship has historically been framed within the notions of administration or management, only
recently has leadership overtaken them as the main descriptor for what is entailed in running and proving public
service organizations (Bush, 2008; Hoyle &Wallace, 2005; Selznick, 1984). Leadership is often linked with
change, vision, values, or purpose, whereas management and administration are related to maintenance,
implementation, or technical issues (Bush, 1998; Cuban, 1998), However, both dimensions of organizational
activity are present and important in the role of school administrators (Bush, 2011). As Hallinger (2003) argued,
leadership perspective on the role of the principal does not diminish the principal's managerial role. Moreover,
Starratt (2004) cautioned about presenting and interpreting issues that school leaders face primarily as
technical, rationalizable problems resolvable by technical, rational solutions, and not surfacing the human, civic,
and moral challenges nested in many of these problems. Similarly, Sergiovanni (1992) implies that technical
expertise without a moral compass is inadequate for the task, as is a moral compass without technical
expertise.
The assertion that educational leadership is a fundamentally moral endeavor has been developed over many
years by numerous scholars (Begley, 1999; Furman, 2004; Greenfield, 2004; Hodgkinson, 1991; Johansson,
2004; Langlois, 2008; Sernak, 1998; Starratt, 1994). A number of theoretical foundations for understanding
ethical leadership have been developed by Nod-dings (1984), Duignan and Bhindi (1997), Strike, Haller, and
Soltis (1988), Kimbrough (1985), Sergiovanni, and Starratt (1991, 2004). Writing on the philosophy of
administration 20 years ago, Hodgkinson encapsulated the "then modern state" of educational leadership when
he termed it "especially difficult, especially challenging and especially moral" and said that it was in essence,
"philosophy-in-action" (pp. 63, 115) We assert that this state remains as Hodgkinson described it: administration
is a moral art that points to our need for wisdom, and "leadership is always a function of value and of
23 October 2014 Page 3 of 26 ProQuestcommitment to organizational value or purpose (p. 27). It is beyond the scope of this article to explicate and
exegete the axiological, epistemological, and ontological presuppositions for this wide-ranging collection of
educational scholars. This has been done elsewhere (Evers &Lakomski, 1990; Hodgkinson, 1978). Nor do we
delve into specific schools or doctrines of ethics as has been done in earlier works (Donlevy &Walker, 2011;
Walker, 1991; Walker &Donlevy, 2006, 2009).
Campbell (1999) observed that central to much of the ethical leadership literature is that "educational leaders
must develop and articulate a much greater awareness of the ethical significance of their actions and
decisions." (p. 152). As Starratt (1991) suggested, ultimately, "educational leaders have a moral responsibility to
be proactive about creating an ethical environment for the conduct of education" (p. 187). In his review of
comparative systems of ethics, Rebore (2001) evoked three justifications for the relevance of ethics in
educational leadership: (a) ethics not only provide a framework for decision-making, but also require reflection
on values; (b) ethics support disciplined ways of thinking; and (c) ethical analysis offers a unique response to
the demands of leadership. Whereas typical leadership approaches, instructional or managerial, might answer
the questions of how and what, a well-developed sense and competence in ethical leadership can help answer
the question of why (Rebore).
In their examination of the daily practices of school administrators, researchers (Langlois, 2004; Langlois
&Starratt, 2001) discovered that certain situations were increasingly challenging for them in terms of how they
justified their decisions and in the difficulty that they experienced in understanding the ethical issues in their
practice. Similarly, Beckner (2004) posited that to many administrators, philosophy and ethics seem rather far
removed from the everyday challenges of educational leadership and management, and they tend to rely more
on experience and personal judgment. However, the influence dimension of leadership requires the leaders to
have an effect on the lives of those being led, so making a change in other people carries with it an enormous
ethical burden and responsibility (Northouse, 2013). Moreover, as Stefkovich (2006) noted,
Ethics should guide school leaders' decision making, [so] that there can be common ground even in
multicultural, pluralistic society, and that, rather than impose their own values on students and teachers, school
leaders should strive to reach a higher moral ground in making decisions, (p. 4)
Applied ethics help educational leadership to move from bureaucratic systems and control toward empowering
teachers and participation in making decisions (Rucinski &Bauch, 2006). Ethical considerations enlarge and
enrich the language and frames of deliberation for school leaders with respect to their professional and moral
purpose, obligations, and agency on behalf of students and other stakeholders. In this article, we position the
best interests of students as an important criterion for ethical deliberation and determinations. A delimitation of
this study is that its context and the selection of literature cited draws primarily on English-speaking,
Commonwealth, and United States contexts. Our interest is to provoke enhanced dialogical competence,
particularly with respect to ethical issues and decisions in schools. Given these assertions, what part do the
interests of students or the best interests of children have in the conduct of education and the ethical
adjudication work of school principals?
Best Interests of Students
The concept of the best interests of the students is most usefully understood in the context of our vision of what
might constitute an ethical framework for those working with children and youth in the educational sector.
Scholars have produced and elaborated multidimensional ethical frameworks (Begley, 2006; Furman, 2004;
Katz, Noddings, &Strike, 1999; Shapiro &Gross, 2008; Shapiro &Hassinger, 2007; Shapiro &Stefkovich, 2001b;
Starratt, 1994; Stefkovich, 2006) that envisage and conceptualize the effect of diverse ethical perspectives on
educational leaders. Shapiro and Hassinger call these perspectives paradigms.
Developed in response to the complex ethical challenges facing contemporary society, the approaches of ethic
of justice, ethic of care, ethic of critique (Starratt, 1994), ethic of profession (Shapiro &Stefkovich, 2001b), and
ethic of community (Furman, 2004) may be drawn together by principals to create an integrated framework for
23 October 2014 Page 4 of 26 ProQuestethical practice. As Starratt noted, the interpénétration of each of these ethical and interpretative themes is
necessary for the fully developed moral person, fully developed human society, and we would add, the agentic
leader. We contend that the ethics described below should not be set in opposition to one another, but viewed
as collectively comprising an ethics system with a web of concepts and applications.
Ethic of Justice
Fairness or equal treatment is the core value underlying an ethic of justice. It focuses on rights and law, as
"society must establish rules that are fair to all and then live by those rules" (Noddings, 1999, p. 8). Starratt
(1994) conceived the ethic of justice as requiring that we "govern ourselves by observing justice" and
henceforth "treat each other according to some standard of justice" (p. 49), which is uniformly applied to all
relationships. For Starratt, this type of ethic emanates from two schools of thought: one, represented by Thomas
Hobbes and John Rawls, advocated for the individual as the primary human reality, independent of social
relationships and logically prior to society who engages in a social contract with the community; and the second,
represented to various degrees by Aristotle, Rousseau, Hegel, Marx, and Dewey, placed the society as the prior
reality in which the individual develops. Although these philosophers came from diverse philosophical traditions
and in some cases diametrically opposed perspectives, they viewed ethics as grounded in practice in the
community. In this regard, the person living in society learns the lessons of morality through experience; and
participation in the life of the community teaches the individual how to think of his or her own behavior in terms
of the larger common good of the community. Starratt (2003) contended that an ethic of justice, especially when
focused on the issues of governance in a school setting, can encompass both understandings: "justice
understood as individual choice to act justly and justice understood as the community's choice to direct or
govern its actions justly" (p. 144).
Denig and Quinn (2001) state that this ethic perceives ethical decision-making as rational, logical, systemic, and
enhanced by universal principles. As such, Shapiro and Hassinger (2007) suggest that this ethic leads in-school
administrators to questions such as: Is there a law, right, or policy that would be appropriate for resolving a
particular ethical dilemma? Why is this law, right, or policy the correct one for this particular case? Does this law
or policy serve our deliberations or adjudication of the best interests of the students? How should the law, right,
or policy be implemented such that students' best interests are served? In summary, the ethic of justice focuses
on rights, law, and policies and concepts such as fairness, equality, and individual freedom.
Ethic of Care
The ethic and concept of care are often described as a relation based on mutual agreement, loyalty, or
alignment. Starratt (1994) denoted that an ethic of care requires "fidelity to persons" and absolute regard and
love. It is concerned less with fairness and more with caring for individuals as unique persons. This ethic is
rooted in the work of Gilligan's (1982) analysis of Kohlberg's moral development and subsequent writers like
Noddings (1984, 2005) and Beck (1994). Its relational nature is reflected in Beck's contention that "the
communal relationships between people mean that the welfare of each is inextricably related to the welfare of
others ... such that caring for others is, in fact, caring for oneself" (p. 20). Rucinski and Bauch (2006) called for
in-school administrators to be grounded in the ethic of care and in belief in the sacredness of human
relationships and the good of human beings in the school organization.
Noddings (2005) and Sergiovanni (1992) have challenged the status of the ethic of justice as dominant among
ethical paradigms in education and law and have called for more attention to concepts such as loyalty, trust,
and empowerment. However, whereas theoretical opposition to the dominance of the ethic of justice advances
theoretical understandings and provides space for the use of the ethic of care, academics routinely call for the
two ethics to be balanced (Sernak, 1998; Shapiro &Hassinger, 2007; Stefkovich, 2006). Stefkovich identified
three factors intrinsic to this concept:
1. Understanding self both as separate from and in relation to community,
2. Building a just and democratic pluralistic school community; and
23 October 2014 Page 5 of 26 ProQuest3. Experiencing personal freedom in order to fully function in a community. (p. 11)
The relationship between the ethic of care and best interests is profound in the light of Rucinski and Bauch's
(2006) call for educational leaders to be grounded in the ethic of care and in belief in the sacredness of human
relationships and the good of human beings in the school organization. Similarly, Shapiro and Hassinger (2007)
suggested that this ethic asks in-school administrators to consider the consequences of their decisions and
actions by taking into account questions such as: Who will benefit from what I decide? Who will be hurt by my
actions? What are the long-term effects of a decision I make today? And if I am helped by someone now, what
should I do in the future about giving back to this individual or to society in general? In summary, the ethic of
care is rooted in relationship-building, trust in, and compassion for others.
Ethic of Critique
The ethic of critique deals with questions of social justice and human dignity and the morality of social and
political resistance (Starratt, 2003). It is aimed at awakening our attention to the inequities found in schools and
in society and represents a challenge to the status quo in order to give a voice to the marginalized (Rucinski
&Bauch, 2006; Stefkovich, 2006). This ethic recognizes that no social arrangement is neutral. Every social
arrangement, no matter how it presents itself, is artificial (Starratt, 1994). Arrangements are usually structured to
benefit some segments of society at the expense of others, and hence the ethical challenge is to make these
social arrangements more responsive to the human and social rights of all citizens, especially the marginalized
and "the least among us." The challenge for educational leaders is to expose and confront the tough questions
of social class, race, gender, and so forth. This ethic requires educators to deal with the hard questions in areas
of difference including: Who makes the laws, rules, or policies? Who benefits from these laws, rules, or
policies? Who has the power? Who are the silenced voices (Shapiro &Hassinger, 2007)? And who says this or
that is an action, accommodation, affordance, or appropriation in the best interests of students? Applying the
ethic of critique may require confronting some entrenched assumptions about the assumed legitimacy of the
status quo and the risk of standing up to superiors who support, even by their own passivity, the status quo
(Starratt, 2010).
The ethic of critique has been elaborated by critical theorists and activists, as well as critical pedagogy theorists
who analyze social class and inequities (Apple, 1988, 2001, 2003; Foucault, 1983; Freire, 1970; Giroux, 1994;
Purpel, 2004; Shapiro, 2006). In this respect, the ethic of critique provides a "discourse in expanding basic
human rights" (Shapiro &Stefkovich, 2001b, p. 14) and the basis for moving from discourse to action. Such a
critique and posture leads to the development of options related to important concepts such as oppression,
power, culture, privilege, authority, voice, language empowerment, and in particular, social justice. In summary,
the ethic of critique is typified by a critical inquiry of differences.
Ethic of Community
Furman (2004) suggested that increased attention be given in the ethics literature to collaborative work and
communal processes necessary to build an ethical school and to achieve the moral purpose of schooling in the
21st century. Furthermore, Furman lamented that ethical frames often do little to pull our thinking beyond the
mindset so entrenched in our Western society of the individual as leader and moral agent. Defined as "the
moral responsibility to engage in communal processes" (p. 215), an ethic of community envisages
administrators, teachers, school staff members, students, parents, and other community members engaging in
communal processes as they pursue the moral purposes of schooling. Thus an ethic of community privileges
the communal over the individual as moral agent. The shift of the locus of moral agency to the community as a
whole is represented as preeminent in relation to the other ethical paradigms. According to Furman, the ethic of
community captures the centrality of this need for communal processes as the ethics of justice, critique, and
care (Starratt, 1994) and the profession (Shapiro &Stefkovich, 2001b) do not. We might ask what we think are
the alternative courses of action that collectively provide for this cohort of students, in this community, given our
values and plural interests. Viewed through the lens of the ethic of community, best interests are community-
23 October 2014 Page 6 of 26 ProQuestminded and pluralistic in nature.
Ethic of Profession
A number of scholars (Beck, 1994; Begley, 1999; Normore, 2004; Shapiro, 2006; Starratt, 2010; Stefkovich,
2006; Willower, 1999) have advocated that school administrators have professional preparation in ethics, and
especially in ethical decision-making. According to Shapiro and Stefkovich (2005), even taken together, the
ethics of justice, critique, and care do not provide an adequate picture of the factors that must be taken into
consideration as leaders strive to make ethical decisions in the context of educational settings. Shapiro and
Stefkovich aptly surmised, "not all those who write about the importance of the study of ethics in educational
administration discuss the needs of children; however, this focus on students is clearly consistent with the
backbone of our profession" (p. 23). They argued that if there were a moral imperative for educational
administration, it would be to serve the best interests of the student and that this ideal would lie at the heart of a
professional paradigm for in-school administrators. Starratt (2004, 2010) argues that an educational leader's
professional ethical responsibility is to promote the good of the practice of the profession, namely, to promote
the good of learning, the good of general education. Shapiro and Hassinger (2007) identify that the lens of the
ethic of the profession to resolve an ethical dilemma raises questions such as, What is in the best interests of
the student? What are the personal and professional codes of an educational leader? What professional
organizations' codes of ethics should be considered in order to best serve the interests of these students? What
does the local community think about this issue? And what is the appropriate way for a professional to act in this
particular situation, based on the standards of practice for the profession?
The ethic of profession takes into account not only the standards of the profession, but also community
standards, the personal and professional codes of an educational leader, and the professional codes of a
number of educational organizations (Shapiro &Stefkovich, 2001a). The integration of personal and professional
codes may lead to a clash of codes that the school leader will need to negotiate. The best interests of the
student is a moral ideal that can be relied on to calm the internal struggle between personal morality, what is
determined as right and good according to the individual, and what an organization and/or the profession
expects, values, and delineates as right and good practice (Frick, 2006). Factors that play in the development of
professional codes may include, but not be limited to, the inclusion of considerations of community standards,
including both the professional community and the community in which the leader works. Stefkovich and
Shapiro (2003) advocate that dialoguing about and in the communities of work to help address the silencing is
especially important to critical theorists. Hence, community is embedded in the model and is not interpreted as a
stand-alone ethic as in Furman's (2004) model. However whether community is viewed as a separate ethic or
part of a larger schema, as positive or negative, its influence on ethical decision-making in schools may be
profound and should not be underestimated (Stefkovich, 2006). Stefkovich summarized that the ethic of
profession asks educational leaders to "to create a dynamic model that places 'the best interests of the student'
as central" (p. 14) and as such is a core moral imperative for educational leaders.
Promoting a Student's Best Interests: Ethical and Jurisprudential Considerations
Of course, ethical decision-making is more easily espoused and intended than it is enacted and implemented. It
is our view that an awareness or consciousness of and language for articulating ethical challenges with respect
to the best interests of students may contribute to better decisions for students. As with earlier explication,
numerous attempts in recent writing on ethical leadership have been made to examine the relationship between
the best-interests principle and decision-making. However, as Clarke et al. (2010) argued, the best interests of
the child test has been criticized for its indeterminacy; simply put, there is no single definition of what is or is not
in the best interests of a child. In the absence of any clear definition of best interests, a guide to determine
factors to be considered in making ethical decisions was developed by Stefkovich (2006) and later elaborated
on by Stefkovich and Begley (2007). This guide for educational leaders in making decisions in the student's best
interest consists of three broadly conceived jurisprudential constructs (by this we mean the understandings from
23 October 2014 Page 7 of 26 ProQuest"regime" law-making and judicial interpretations in case law): rights, responsibility, and respect. These concepts
incorporate Walker's (1998a) claim to ground educational decisions and policies in ethics and jurisprudence.
Relying on context, this conceptualization takes into account students' voices and begins with the assumption
that school officials will engage in active inquiry and self-reflection in order to make decisions that are truly in
the best interests of the student rather than self-serving or merely expedient (Stefkovich &Begley).
Rights are essential to determining a student's best interests and include: rights granted to all human beings as
articulated by philosophers past and present; and universal rights recognized by the United Nations, and
particularly those rights acknowledged under its Convention on the Rights of the Child. The use of the best-
interests construct and approach to decision-making is evident in judicial cases across the Commonwealth
nations, in Europe, and in states associated with the United Nations. In addition, this approach recognizes the
existence of certain fundamental rights as universal despite the fact that some countries seem not to have fully
recognized them in practice (Bitensky, 1992). As a result, caution is warranted when using the word universal to
differentiate ideals from realities and to acknowledge the difference between jurisprudential principle and
alignment of intention to actual behavior and decision-making in educational practice and experience.
Although individual rights are fundamental, they are not unfettered (Stefkovich, 2006). Accordingly, we advocate
an approach that honors the philosophical tradition of accompanying rights with responsibility. Indeed, theorists
past and present from many diverse perspectives consider rights to be incomplete if viewed without
consideration of accompanying responsibilities. Although not based directly on utilitarian ethics, John Stuart
Mill's words on responsibility are viewed as significant: "Everyone who receives the protection of society owes a
return for the benefit, and the fact that living in society renders it indispensable that each should be bound to
observe a certain line of conduct toward the rest" (1978, cited in Stefkovich, 2006, p. 23). Noteworthy is the
differentiation between two major orientations of the term responsibility (Jonsen, 1968): the ex post
responsibility of attribution (i.e., holding responsibility for the commission of an act), and the ex ante
responsibility of appropriation (i.e., antecedent responsibility on the event or activity). Influenced by Locke,
Rousseau, and Kant, contemporary scholars have connected ethical decision-making with the latter orientation
to responsibility that one has in making moral choices. This pattern of thinking about responsibility is concerned
with a more general sense of expectations that in a given role, one will perform as a morally responsible agent
(Starratt, 2004). Inclusion of responsibility in the conceptualization of the best interests of students is supported
by Starratt (2005), Gilligan (1982), and Noddings (2002), each of whom recognized the concepts of authentic
self and empathy.
The concept of respect has been applied to ethics across many disciplines and arises in each of the five ethics
that we delineate in this article. There is no agreement as to a central definition, and philosophers often
conceptualize respect through the Golden Rule. Most often the respect-of-persons doctrine is equated with the
work of Kant, who proffered respect for persons as central to moral theory. In the light of an array of definitions
of respect, Stefkovich (2006) offered Kant's placement of respect in moral theory as a foundation to its inclusion
in her model, and as such it means to treat others never as a means to ends, but as ends. The best-interests
model conceptualizes respect as a cornerstone of ethical behavior that requires positive, mutual interactions
between individuals. Stefkovich envisaged respect as including equity, equality, tolerance, self-respect,
acceptance, and "a commitment to finding common ground in an increasingly multicultural, pluralistic society"
(p. 26).
The ethics and jurisprudential literature impart a continued concern with the nature of the principle and the
process of determining best interests, resulting in continual reflection and critique. Stefkovich's (2006) best-
interests model sought to provide a jurisprudentially and ethically defensible expression of what is in a student's
best interests and to assist educational leaders in understanding that self-reflection, open-mindedness, and
sensitivity are necessary qualities and that making ethically sound decisions profoundly influences others' lives
(Frick, 2006). Consequently, the "myriad of considerations" that are imposed in resolutions of best interests
23 October 2014 Page 8 of 26 ProQuestimpose a great deal of pressure on decision-makers to use their ethical discretion and dialogical competence
(Walker, 1998a, p. 293). Educators are best informed as to the extent and depth of best interests through
considerations of ethical and jurisprudential interpretations.
Educational leaders increasingly deal with questions about who holds the overriding authority in decisions about
particular children. Walker (1998a) claimed that it may be wise to exchange the question "What is best for these
children?" with the question "Who should decide what is best for these children?" Walker (1998b) articulated
this modern conundrum when he wrote, "Sometimes parents, educational professionals, special interests
groups, state representatives of justice, education and social services all vie for legal position and pre-
eminence" (p. 321). He contended that educational leaders were well positioned to help negotiate among
various stakeholders and indeed state that it is the core responsibility of educational leaders to work with their
collaborators to mediate competing interests and for "collaborative processes to bring grassroots expertise to
bear on decisions that make a difference for children" (p. 320). Hodgkinson (1991) rather famously argued that
educational administration finds itself in a rather special-case position among administrative professions:
Its leaders find themselves in what might be called an arena of ethical excitement-often politicized but always
humane, always intimately connected to the evolution of society, sometimes invested with the Type I values of
the culture. Besides, education is both an institution in the sociological sense and a vested interest in the
political science sense. It embodies a heritage of value, on the one hand, and is a massive industry on the
other, in which social, economic, and political forces are locked together in a complex equilibrium of power, (p.
164)
He concluded that all these factors call for extraordinary value sensitivity on the part of educational leaders.
Beyond the extant literature on the best interests of students, just how do the principals as leaders understand
and make use in practice of the concept of the best interests of students? This was the question that we sought
to explore in the study described below.
Methodology
Our purpose for the research was to examine the best-interests principle through an investigation of theory,
practice, and professional praxis and thus to identify the common use and understanding of the best-interests
principle in Canadian in-school administrative practice. This study is a subset of an extensive examination of the
Canadian school principals' perceptions of their moral agency, ethical problems, challenges, pressures, and
influences at work and grounds for their ethical decision-making and recovering of trust in schools. This article
selectively deals with the participants' perceptions of the principle of best interests of children/students as it
applied to their principalship. Five research questions guided the study: How do in-school administrators define
and use best interests? In what circumstances do in-school administrators use best interests? What factors
influence their decisions of best interest? How do in-school administrators make determinations of best
interests? and What is the extent of in-school administrators' conceptualization of best interests?
The target population for this study included Canadian in-school administrators. We asked a stratified sample of
780 in-school administrators to participate in the survey. The participants were identified by an analysis of
multiple educational databases at the national, provincial, and divisional levels. Of the total number of surveys
distributed (N=780), 17% or 132 in-school administrators chose to participate in the study. Although the sample
represented all Canadian provinces and territories, we note that three of the 13 jurisdictions had a
disproportionately higher response rate. The participants were all practicing in-school administrators throughout
Canada.
As a primary data-collection tool for this study, we administered a survey in both mail-out and on-line forms. The
best interests questionnaire, consisting of 14 closed- and open-ended questions, was embedded in a larger
study survey on moral agency and trust that fielded five questionnaires: two online versions and three mailed
versions. Embedded into the online versions and two of the three mailed versions, the survey was distributed to
a stratified sample of in-school administrators across Canada. We developed items for the instrument based on
23 October 2014 Page 9 of 26 ProQuestrecommendations from principals and questions raised in the literature. To check for content validity, we field-
tested the survey with a group of principals and a panel of experts reviewed it before distribution.
In this study, the quantitative and qualitative data were not prioritized. Instead, we collected quantitative and
qualitative data, weighted them equally, and analyzed them in a complementary manner. The closed-question
data consisted of attitude-scaled questions that ascertained the principals' use and application of the best-
interests concept. We recorded the responses to attitude questions on a five-point Likert scale, which asked
participants to check their level of agreement with various statements. We sought further exploration of use and
application of the best-interests principle through open-ended questions.
We subjected the quantitative data from the 11 closed attitudinal ques- tions to descriptive statistical analysis to
identify central categories. We provide simple percentages of responses with means and standard deviations,
but note the uneven cell sizes and response rate due to variance in completed mail-out and on-line versions of
the survey. We subjected the qualitative data from the open-ended questions to thematic analysis. We grouped
the results of the analyses of qualitative data and presented them according to emergent themes. Responses to
open-ended questions were coded according to the dominant recurring themes in the responses (MacMillan
&Schumacher, 2006). Codes were then combined into categories, and categories into patterns or concepts
(Lichtman, 2010). Analysis of open-ended responses provided rich descriptive data for the study.
The demographic data for the study included six categories: age, gender, province, years of professional
experience, years of experience as a princi- pal, and formal ethical training (See Table 1).
The participating principals fitted into four age-range categories; most (81%) belonged to the 41-60 age group.
Gender representation showed a slight prevalence of male principals. Two thirds of the respondents had 21 or
more years as a professional educator, and most had held administrative positions for up to 10 years.
More than three quarters of the participants held master's and a few had doctoral degrees. More than half
reported some formal training in ethics, which consisted of university-level courses in ethics or ethical
23 October 2014 Page 10 of 26 ProQuestleadership as well as board or school professional development activities (or a combination of both).
Research Findings: Principals' Perceptions of the Best-Interests Principle
The findings were grouped into the following categories: definitions and significance of the best-interests
principle; familiarity, use, and efficacy of the best-interests principle; preference for resolving best interests
individually or communally; and ethical paradigm preferences in resolving best-interests dilemmas.
Definition and Description of the Best-Interests Concept
Given the view in the literature that educational leaders frequently justify their actions as in the best interests of
children, we were interested in their definitions and perceptions of the significance of the best-interests principle.
In this section we discuss data from the following open-ended questions: How do you prefer to define "in the
best interests of the student(s)"? How would you explain "in the best interests of the student(s)" to a new staff
member? We were not expecting different responses to these questions, but rather chose to ask the descriptive
and definitional question in two ways.
Analyses of the data revealed that the notion of the best interests of the student(s) was broadly conceptualized
and defined in three major categories of thought: best interests as core good, best interests as good pedagogy,
and best interests as comprehensive good. Most respondents identified with a definition of best interests as a
core good. The best interests of students were regularly described as the core or center of decision-making and
the heart of educators' work. One respondent noted, "I would ask staff members to always remember why we
teach-to educate students. They are our priority." It was evident that the respondents mitigated decisions of best
interests by placing the students at the heart of decision-making, or as one respondent articulated, "We need to
see to their needs ahead of our own." Prevalently, respondents defined best interests as the why of their work
and why they entered teaching. Respondents identified an ethical duty and responsibility toward providing
students with the best possible care and attention including decisions on their behalf. This sense of service
responsibility prevailed that: "Students are our client and we have a responsibility to our students" and that an
agreed central purpose of education, best interests, should be "to serve students." Finally, respondents defined
best interests as the best outcome or as a positive benefit. Decision-making in this manner was depicted as
those decisions that led to students' development, advancement, and growth. One comment encapsulates this
point: "What the phrase [best interest] means to me is that decisions are made from the perspective of providing
the best possible outcome for that child."
When describing best interests as good pedagogy, principals used concepts and phrases like learning,
achievement, learning environment, and pedagogy. The best-interests principle was described as a means to
an end. In the view of some respondents, the central purpose or paramount reason for education was students'
learning as indicated in the following responses: "Our central purpose is student learning. I prefer to define 'best
interests' in the context of good pedagogy," and "I would explain it by saying that the paramount reason we are
in business is to advance student learning. If the decision advances student learning, then it is in the best
interest of the student." Decisions of best interests were identified by the respondents as those that "supported]
student learning [and] achievement in a safe and caring learning environment" or enabled students to "flourish
in an environment that is safe and productive to learning." In addition, the respondents defined decisions of best
interests as "interests that [led] to growth through learning opportunities" and higher achievement."
Finally, respondents defined best interests as a comprehensive good, wherein decision processes acknowledge
the complexity of educating students and recognize their multi-faceted lives. Respondents indicated that the
"best interests of the students has to embrace academic, social, emotional, spiritual and intellectual criteria [and
as such] the entire student has to be safeguarded." This way of thinking extended interests beyond narrow
interpretations. Whereas others might have depicted student learning or good pedagogy as the center, these
respondents envisaged a larger holistic context for the definition of best interests such that decisions were best
considered when "all the needs, dimensions and variables of student life" are accounted for.
As might have been expected, in defining best interests, the respondents identified three types of influences
23 October 2014 Page 11 of 26 ProQuestthat regulated, affected, and in some cases mitigated decisions in the best interests of student(s): stakeholders'
influence, contextual considerations, and relational aspects. Respondents' definitions of best interests were
mitigated by a sense that all of those involved in a decision, the stakeholders, should be considered.
Furthermore, decisions of best interest needed to consider the multiple stakeholders' needs, present and future.
At the same time, it was indicated that sometimes it might be necessary to override the influence of some
stakeholders in order not to jeopardize the best interests of the student(s). Respondents identified a range of
contextual considerations based on the availability and breadth of information about the situation. For example,
one participant noted that the information one has regarding a student's situation must come into play for each
decision made: "In the best interest of the student is a phrase used by people who believe that their decisions
and actions can affect the lives of the student(s) in their care ... Decisions are based on information: the better
the information the better the decision and how it will affect people." Finally, respondents indicated that
decisions of best interest needed to consider relational aspects together with the importance and significance of
attending to relationships among students and staff. One respondent wrote that best-interests decisions were
best made in the context of getting to know student(s) on a "personal level" and to "understand who they are as
people." The implication was that determinations of best interests are predicated on fostering honest, respectful,
and open relationships. Respondents also noted that open and positive communication and dialogue were
considered essential to the actualization of best interests. This raises the question of individual and collective
perspectives on the best interests of the students, which we address below.
Familiarity, General Use, and Perceived Efficacy
Participants were asked to describe the familiarity, general use, and perceived efficacy of the in the best
interests of the student(s) principle. Their responses are outlined in Table 2.
Most of the respondents indicated either strong agreement or agreement with the familiarity of the best-interests
principle and claimed to use the concept routinely in their administrative decision-making. Eighty-six percent of
the respondents strongly agreed or agreed that the best-interests principle was an efficacious means of
resolving ethical challenges in administrative decision-making. The efficacy of the best-interests principle
registered a higher percentage of neutral responses (13%) than that of familiarity and use.
The use of the best-interests principle, further explored in the open-ended questions, revealed five broad
circumstances where in-school administrators used best interests as a means of decision-making: discipline
matters, pedagogical considerations, human resources, special education, and safety. Most frequently,
respondents identified discipline as a time when the notion of best interests was used to justify a decision. The
discipline cases provided by the respondents ranged from alternate options to suspension and expulsion,
safety, and the general enforcement of school rules and expectations. Examples of the cases discussed and
elaborated on included giving a student coaching and extra chances based on his or her background and recent
23 October 2014 Page 12 of 26 ProQuestbehavior, shortening suspensions given individual circumstances even if in conflict with policy, contravening the
practice of contacting parents if family dynamics did not support contact, providing in-school suspensions when
home life was unsafe or when overriding the wishes of teachers. However, even more compelling than the
particulars of the discipline cases was the emergence of three themes discussed above: the need to recognize
the individual student, the influence of stakeholders, and the need to attend to matters such as relationship-
building and dialogue.
Pedagogical instances like learning, programming, or scheduling were also frequently mentioned as deliberative
times when the concept of best interests was used to justify a decision. Some of the pedagogical cases
discussed and elaborated on included learning adaptations for individual needs' student placement, retention,
and advancement; and programming suited to learning and students. Instances of using the best interests to
justify a decision in areas of human resources and staffing showed that the principle had become the mitigating
factor in resolving matters such as possible staffing reassignments, hiring or termination of teaching and support
staff, and staff disciplinary or supervisory matters. As one respondent wrote, "I had to decide whether I could
sacrifice 2.5 teacher associate positions so I could keep a full-time teacher. My decision was made upon the
best interests of the students." In terms of special education, respondents identified the philosophy and nature
of inclusion and the practical means of integration as most common incidences when a best-interests
justification was used. Least frequent was the mention of the best-interests principle in potential unsafe or
supervisory practices where the resolution of the matter was mired in conflict between or among staff, parents,
students, or community expectations of safety.
Preference to Resolving Best-Interests Dilemmas: Individual or Collective
In-school administrators were asked to indicate a preference for resolving matters of best interests as either
upholding the individual (student) or the communal (students) interests. Their responses are outlined in Table 3.
Most participating school administrators (83%) strongly agreed that the optimal test of a difficult ethical situation
was whether the decision supported the best interests of all students. On the other hand, a more moderate
percentage of principals (64%) agreed that the optimal test of a difficult situation was whether the decision
supported the best interests of the individual student.
Participants' verbatim responses added more clarity on the collective or individual use of the best-interests
principle as an optimal test. Despite the widespread articulation that most students' interests should take
precedence, many respondents acknowledged the recognition of individual students' needs. Of course, this
course of inquiry was highly dependent on situations imagined or experienced by the respondents. However,
most of the respondents identified the need for a balanced approach in weighing the interests of the collective
student body and each individual student: "We always need to do what is in the best interest of individual
students; however, we must be aware of the message decisions send for the collective learning community we
23 October 2014 Page 13 of 26 ProQuestserve." With this comes the difficulty of being multifocused or "keeping in mind the student's welfare (physical,
intellectual, emotional), including the balancing of individual and common needs when making decisions."
Instrumental in this test was the relation of the best-interests-of-students principle with the notions of fairness
and equality, or as one principal phrased it, "Fair is not equal; fair is giving everyone what they need, but yet
what is best for each child."
Ethical Paradigm Preference in Resolving Best-Interests Dilemmas
In order to assess how educational leaders make determinations in the best interest of the student(s) and what
factors influenced those decisions, respondents were asked to identify their attitude to five ethical paradigms
influencing their decisions: justice, care, critique, profession, and community. Participating principals' responses
to survey questions and the corresponding ethical paradigms are shown in Table 4.
Analysis of attitudinal questions revealed that respondents rated the ethic of care highly among the ethical
paradigms. The ethic of critique and professional code of ethics received a similar rating behind the ethic of
care, and the ethics of justice and community received lower rankings among the ethical paradigms.
Respondents were not given extended definitions of these ethical paradigms, but rather responded to nominal,
descriptive statements. As such, we offer these findings only as possible signals of respondents' dispositions
toward each ethical paradigm.
The qualitative data provided somewhat different results, whereas frequency of mention and significance
assigned by respondents to each ethic confirmed a ranked preference ranging from the ethic of care, ethic of
critique, ethic of profession, ethic of community, and ethic of justice. Analysis of these data revealed that the
respondents had not envisaged best interests in discrete terms, but rather in a complex manner consisting of
multiple or mixed ethical paradigms. The high incidences of the ethic of care among the qualitative data were
comparable to the quantitative data results. Respondents repeatedly articulated an emphasis on relationships,
dialogue, and integrity of the student or stakeholder involved. In the words of one principal, "I need students to
23 October 2014 Page 14 of 26 ProQuesttrust that I will put them first. I need the teachers to trust I will support them. I need parents to know I will do
everything possible to provide the best for their children."
Similarly, ways of thinking consistent with the ethic of justice and critique also prevailed in the open-ended
responses. Verbatim statements elicited from the participants revealed that they made considerations of equity
and fairness, as well as giving attention to voice and social justice, in their deliberations and perceptions of best
interest. Minimal references were made to specific codes and responsibilities of in-school administrators within
specific provincial and district regions that guided best interests. Rather, analysis suggested a widespread
recognition or universal acceptance of general, philosophical standards of the profession and of educators in
general, that is, the purpose and heart of best interests were the student and students.
Whereas analysis of the quantitative data indicated that respondents ranked considerations of the ethic of
community low among other ethical considerations, analysis of the qualitative data revealed a higher and more
significant role for this ethic. A prevalent theme among respondents' data was attention to communal manners
of thinking and behaving consistent with ethic of community, communication, collaboration, dialogue, and
stakeholders' involvement. In regard to the ethic of community, we found that "best interest of the school
community" and "accountability to the school community" were common descriptors. Community served as a
catalyst for one principal's decisions: "In my community, there is always talk about decisions being made. Often
the blame is placed upon me. I however feel confident knowing I have made a decision in the best interest of
the students."
Further to the above, principals were asked to tell about specific examples of the practical application of the
notion of best interests of students. Several of the participating administrators described working with certain
initiatives in the best interests of students.
* We started a program for autistic students and decided to embrace an inclusive school model in delivering that
program. This was in the best interest of all students and so we moved to support and promote that model. It
was hard because we were asking staff to teach and organize in a way that was different from the norm.
* I have kept students from going to the adjacent lot owned and equipped by the Community's recreation
association during school time as there is not adequate supervision for these students while they are over there.
Our school board does not provide supervision off property-it's not a risk I am willing to take.
* During staffing I have assigned teaching duties to a teacher because he was the best qualified rather than
assign the course to a teacher who did not have the qualifications but wanted the course.
* Students were out at recess and one student got upset with another and punched the student, then removed
himself from the situation on his own accord. I decided not to follow through on a suspension for the student as
he had made a conscious decision to stop and get out of the situation. Teacher wanted me to suspend, but I felt
that the student would learn more by working the situation through and working with the student he had trouble
with.
* Students were assigned to work as a small group on a cooperative activity; one student really wanted to work
alone and had shown us that it was the best way for him to stay on task and produce his best work. He was
allowed to work alone and the other two students worked as a pair.
Through analysis of these findings, we have glimpsed into and worked to grasp the array of situations entailed
in the work of principals who indirectly and directly wonder what might be in the best interests of the students
under their care. How might we understand the interpretations and use that principals seem to make of the
notion of the best interests of students?
Discussion: Best-Interests Model and the Educational Leader
As observed in the findings, the participating Canadian in-school administrators conceived the principle in best
interests of the student(s) in ways somewhat consistent with the professional ethic and best interests models in
the literature. Yet their conception of best interests moved beyond the current models and literature to include
best interests as moral imperative. They reaffirmed the multidimensional ethical framework (ethics of justice,
23 October 2014 Page 15 of 26 ProQuestcare, critique, and profession) and placed emphasis on an emerging role of the ethic of community.
Moral Imperative: Best Interests of Student(s)
This study affirmed the importance of moral and ethical considerations in educational administration. The
findings support Foster's (1986) observation that each administrative decision carries with it a restructuring of
human life and, therefore, administration at its heart is the resolution of moral dilemmas. Furthermore, as
Stefkovich (2006) contends, "it is incumbent on school leaders to make ethical decisions that truly reflect the
needs of the students and not their own self-interests ... it requires a great deal of self-reflection, open-
mindedness, and an understanding that making ethically sound decisions profoundly influences others' lives" (p.
21). These authors, with Hodgkinson (1991), suggest that there is a moral art to educational leadership that
differentiates or even distinguishes the role from more mechanical, rational-technical, and managerial roles. The
stewardship of vulnerable children and the entrustment of parents, state, and community obligate educational
leaders to high standards of care and moral deliberation.
Participants affirmed the "contested nature of educational problem-solving" (Begley &Zaretsky, 2004, p. 653)
and revealed a dichotomy of conceiving best interests. Whereas defining best interests as the ethical foundation
for educational decision-making was evident, the data also suggest that interests were simultaneously narrowly
and broadly defined such as in pedagogical and comprehensive-good definitions.
Respondents conveyed the effect of the clash of interests on educational decision-making by identifying the
possible limitations. They concurred that although identifying best interests was a complicated and difficult task,
adherence to the principle was still just and right despite those challenges. As Vojak (2003) notes, even if one
acknowledges that best interests are not always discernible, it should not keep one from striving toward best
interests as an ideal. In this respect the data indicate that the best-interests principle plays a significant role in
directing the reasoning, judgment, and deliberation of in-school administrators.
This conception of the best-interests principle echoes the prevalent argument in the literature that the principle
of best interests is an ideal. The respondents in this study consistently identified in their definitions that the
principle of best interests was the guiding purpose of educational administration and as such the core good of
sound decision-making. In addition, social and moral duties that underpin the jurisprudential construct of
responsibility were also evident in the data. As Kopelman (1997) noted, "best interests standard makes little
sense unless it is understood not as an absolute duty, but as a prima facie duty or an ideal that should guide
choices" (p. 277). As an ideal construct, the best interests of students may be seen as a lighthouse giving us
perspective and helping us steer or navigate our best course on behalf of students. Research on how principals
respond when confronted with ethical dilemmas suggests that the best interests of students figure prominently
as a meta-organizer and ultimate influence on their decision-making (Stefkovich &Begley, 2007).
Multidimensional Ethical Framework
The current literature continues to emphasize the significance of the ethics of justice, care, critique, and
profession for real-life ethical dilemmas in leadership practices of in-school administrators (Langlois &Lapointe,
2007; Shapiro &Stefkovich, 2011). The first three ethics have been frequently discussed in the field of
educational leadership. Starratt (2003) argued that each ethic needs the strong connections embedded in the
other; the ethic of justice needs profound commitment to the dignity of the individual person and the profound
social analysis of the ethic of critique; the ethic of care needs the larger attention to social order and fairness;
and the ethic of critique requires an ethic of care if it is to avoid the cynical and depressing ruminations of the
habitual malcontent.
This study reinforced the interconnectedness of the three ethics in the ethical decision-making of in-school
administrators. Incidences of thinking consistent with the three ethics were prevalent in the data. In many cases,
the responses of the in-school administrators exhibited the complexity and layering of ethical
interconnectedness. In-school administrators tended to balance the students' right to learning (ethic of justice),
the comprehensive needs of the student (ethic of care), students' self-interests (ethic of justice/ care), and the
23 October 2014 Page 16 of 26 ProQuesteffect on current/future student relationships (ethic of critique). This finding may be attributed to the years of
experience, as most of the respondents in this study had been in administrative positions for six or more years,
and almost a quarter had 11 or more years of experience. The interconnectedness of ethics allows for fuller
expression of ethical leadership and is linked to the number of years of experience gained as a principal;
experience is a key factor in the development of a professional ethic that is reflexive rather than procedural
(Langlois &Lapointe, 2007).
Recently, Shapiro and Stefkovich (2011) reinforced the existence of the fourth ethic, that of profession, in a
stand-alone form. Their concept of professional ethics as an ethical paradigm includes ethical principles and
codes of ethics embodied in the ethic of justice, as well as professional judgment and decision-making. They
recognize professional ethics as a dynamic process requiring administrators to develop their own personal and
professional codes. Shapiro and Stefkovich believe that educational leaders should be given the opportunity to
take the time to develop their own personal codes of ethic based on life stories and critical incidents, and create
their professional codes based on the experiences and expectations of their working lives as well as a
consideration of their personal codes. This sense of self as an administrator and its connection to best interests
was evident in our study. As one respondent wrote, best interests are best defined and achieved by "putting
one's own biases, prejudices and preconceptions aside and dealing with the student(s) as an individual-a
student-centered approach where the dignity of the individual must remain intact-where the adult must act in a
reasonable way and with common sense." However, minimal references were made to specific professional
codes and responsibilities in various provincial and district jurisdictions that guided best interests; instead, it was
the universal standards of the profession-that students are the purpose and heart of best interests-that guided
principals' work.
This study emphasized the significance of the ethic of community in a conception of best interests. Shapiro and
Stefkovich (2001b, 2011) and Stefkovich (2006) place the ethic of community in the larger context of the
multidimensional ethical framework and their proposed professional ethic, whereas Furman (2004) advocates
for a wholly distinct and separate conception. Furman's approach differs from those of scholars who view
community as an entity and/or see it in relation to the individual and thus join it with another paradigm (Beck,
1994; Purpel, 2004; Sergiovanni, 1992; Shapiro &Stefkovich, 2011). In Furman's depiction of the ethic of
community, emphasis is placed on the communal and methodological modes of thinking including those of
communication, collaboration, dialogue, and stakeholders' involvement.
The significance of stakeholders' involvement was denoted by the respondents as one of the three major
influences on decisions of best interests, whereas the importance of communication, dialogue, and relationship-
building was evident among all three broad categories of thought defining best interests. In addition, the notion
of a community of educators with a common vision pointed to the collective nature of best interests. The data
echo the African proverb that it takes a village to raise a child and thus views the child not as a product of
individual effort, but of collective interaction and intervention. However, Noddings (2002) issued a warning that
communities can act like bloated individuals. To offset this possibility of bloatedness or groupthink, Noddings
suggested that individuals acquire the ability to accept the ideas and commitments of the community while
resisting community pressures for conformity or orthodoxy. To accomplish this vision, one must have self-
knowledge, but also a knowledge of others that is gained through ongoing communication (Stefkovich, 2006).
However, despite the occurrence of communication, collaboration, dialogue, and stakeholders' involvement in
the data, incidences of expressions of the ethic of community occurred in relation to other ethical positions and
not in isolation. That is, the ethic of community was not conceived discretely, but in unison with other ethical
paradigms of justice, care, critique, and profession. The inclusion of the ethic of community among the other
ethics in the data extends the interconnectedness and complexity of ethical decision-making (Shapiro
&Stefkovich, 2011; Starratt, 2003; Stefkovich, 2006).
23 October 2014 Page 17 of 26 ProQuestAs shown in Figure 1, the best-interests principle was viewed by the principals as the center or heart of their
work (Bishop-Yong, 2010). The interconnectedness of the four ethics of care, justice, critique, and profession
included communal practices of communication, dialogue, collaboration, and stakeholders' involvement to bear
on decisions of best interests. However, this model must be interpreted in conjunction with the discussion of
individual versus collective and subjective versus objective interpretations of best interests.
Best-Interests Dichotomies
Conceptualizing the ethical interpretations of the best-interests principle is premised on the relational nature of
interests. As such, two central dichotomies emerge in interpretations of the best-interests principle in the ethical
literature, and it forms a matrix of best interests: individual versus collective and subjective versus objective (see
Figure 2). Other ways of expressing this dichotomy would be "ad hoc versus criteria-based" decisions or "act
versus rule" decisions. Walker (1998b) suggested that "where the subjective and objective elaborations,
sensitivities, interpretations, and applications meet" (p. 323), we will see the best interest of children and child.
Data analysis revealed a central position of in-school administrators vis àvis best interests on the matrix, where
in the light of legislation, public policy, and ethics, they have to choose an interest to uphold-the individual
(student) or the communal (students) and a methodology of deciding-subjective (case by case) or objective
(criteria based).
The matrix represents the arguments of several theorists on best interests such as Smith (1998), Capron
(1982), Walker (1998a) and Shapiro and Stefkovich (2002b) along the intersecting dichotomies. Smith, like the
judiciary, was concerned with the child in his critique of best interests per the educational leader. According to
Smith, there may be "no singular right, good, or virtuous pattern for all children," yet there may be a singularly
right response for the single child and what fundamentally determines the measure of help given the child is the
moral agency of "people [who] are in better positions relative to particular children than others" (p. 309).
Similarly, Shapiro and Stefkovich and Stefkovich (2006) centered their research on assisting those in "better
23 October 2014 Page 18 of 26 ProQuestpositions"-in-school administrators-to make ethical decisions in the best interests of the student. The underlying
assumpFi tion is that if the individual is treated with fairness, justice, and caring, then a strong message is sent
to all students that they will be afforded justice and caring and that they should treat others similarly
(Stefkovich). However, unlike Smith's assessment, Shapiro and Stefkovich appeared to hold the position of
whose interests, individual or collective, in a balance. Dworkin (1982) identified that the struggle for balancing
the interests of the individual and the communal lies in terms of not only value conflicts, but also time conflicts.
Writing about political representatives, he suggests that they are asked to balance the interests and desires of
some against those of others and may have to consider the interests of current generations against the needs
or interests of future generations. Once again, the nature of interests is relational.
In regard to individualistic notions of the best interest of a child or student, Smith (1998) advocated a singularly
subjective standard. Shapiro and Stefkovich's (2001b, 2005) models conversely advance a blended approach
by proposing a subjective, case-by-case analysis and an objective assessment of multidimensional ethical
paradigms and jurisprudential concepts. Capron (1982) identified the subjective and objective tension inherent
in instances of child-custody disputes and identified that the judiciary and related doctrine "seems to rest on an
'objective' standard of what a reasonable person would find appropriate for the ordinary child" (p. 126). In
application, Capron noted that this standard may amount to a highly subjective decision, but only subjective in
the sense that it reflects the values and beliefs of the judiciary, not those of its individual wards. This values
tension of the individual is reflected in Shapiro and Stefkovich's (2001b) and Frick's (2006) work on the conflicts
of personal and professional codes of ethics and their effect on mediating decisions for the best interest of the
student. Walker (1998b) echoes the tension between subjective and objective determinations of best interest in
his writings on best interests. Although he acknowledges the limited influence of subjective perspectives on
decisions of best interests, he insists on reserving the capacity for "community, parents and professional
magistrates to adjudicate these perspectives by independent and external criteria when conflicts arise." Walker
not only surmises the complexity and relational nature of objectivity and collectivism, but also hints at the
process that influences position on the matrix.
The views of the participating principals were premised on a balanced resolution of best interests using both a
subjective and an objective consideration. Among the best interests conceptualizations-the definitions, use,
influence factors, and how best-interests decisions were made-both objective and subjective considerations
were evident in respondents' thinking. Despite the occurrence of objective criteria such as pedagogical and
23 October 2014 Page 19 of 26 ProQuestcomprehensive considerations (academic, social, behavioral, emotional, spiritual, and intellectual) in defining
best interests, subjective considerations such as stakeholders' influence, contextual considerations, and
relational aspects influenced the position of this study on the matrix.
Despite a stronger preference in the quantitative data to consider the needs of all students rather than the
individual student, analysis of the qualitative data revealed a slight preference for considering the needs of the
individual. Respondents identified a range of contextual considerations including situational factors, weighing
the interests of the greater good and the individual student, as well as recognizing a balance therein. In matters
of discipline and special education, analysis revealed respondents' strong preference for recognizing individual
needs. In matters of human resources, analysis revealed a strong preference for considering the needs of all
students or communal needs. In pedagogical and safety matters, analysis revealed an equitable consideration
of individual and communal needs. In addition, the respondents' emphasis on respect, relationships, voice, and
dialogue in resolving matters of best interest articulated a tension between exclusively defining best interests in
either individual or collective terms. Balancing the notion of the ethical person (Starratt, 1994) with conceptions
of community (Furman, 2004) means balancing self-interests with the interests of students and other
stakeholders and implies reconciling the purposes of personal and professional codes and of education itself.
The principals' responses reported here exemplify this balancing effort.
The results of the study support Gathercoal's (1991) metaphor that "having your cake and eating it too requires
the ingredients of law, education, and ethics, mixed and stirred judiciously with firsthand experience and baked
at a public school setting until it rises to the occasion" (p. 122). The complexity of the context in which outcomes
and decisions of best interests of children are determined by the principals and leaders was articulated as the
need to balance the two intersecting dichotomies on the matrix. These findings lend hope to the creation of
more effective educative communities among in-school administrators (Walker, 1995).
Concluding Remarks
In the changing and challenging operational environment in which schools now operate, "it is not surprising that
educational leaders are often faced with ethical dilemmas in the course of their daily work as they endeavor to
make complex decisions in the best interests of both staff and students" (Cranston et al., 2006, p. 106). The
best interests models such as ethic of profession (Shapiro &Stefkovich, 2001) and a model for promoting a
student's best interests (Stefkovich, 2006) responded to their desire to make sense of a much used, yet
amorphous concept. Stefkovich (2006) identified the pressing need for a codified approach to best interests as
follows.
Understanding that adults possess a great deal of power in determining students' best interests and realizing
how easy it is to ignore the voices of those who literally have the most to lose, it is incumbent upon school
leaders to make ethical decisions that truly reflect the needs of students and not their own adult self-interest, (p.
21)
School principals as formal school leaders are positioned to function as mediators and animators of many
competing and complementary values and interests on behalf of various educational constituents (Walker,
1998a). In their work, the best-interests principle becomes a widely used ethical, legal, and social basis for
making policy and decisions involving children (Kopelman, 1997; Walker, 1995). In this article, we aspire to
provoke educators to engage in further conversations about the best interests of students and provide an
overview of a recent study of the concept as it is understood and used by Canadian school principals. We
discuss the moral nature of educational leadership through a multidimensional ethical framework that comprises
ethics of justice, care, critique, community, and profession. The research reported is intended to examine the
best-interests principle as commonly used and understood in Canadian in-school administrative practice. This
approach results in the presentation of a pluralistic and quasi-consensual articulation of the best interests of
students. We suggest that each of the ethical paradigms presented here will yield unique and valuable
perspectives beyond those offered by our respondents.
23 October 2014 Page 20 of 26 ProQuestForemost in this study is the affirmation of the constructs of the professional ethic and best-interests models
such as the significance of the multi-ethical paradigms and jurisprudential constructs of responsibility, respect,
and rights in educational administrative decision-making. The findings suggest that the respondents have not
envisaged best interests in discrete terms, but rather in a complex manner consisting of multiple or mixed
ethical paradigms. Based on their perspectives, a model of professional ethics and best interests depicts a
balanced use of the ethical paradigms of care, critique, and justice with the intertwined aspects of the ethic of
community, namely, communication, dialogue, collaboration, and stakeholders' involvement. The results of this
study place in-school administrators vis àvis best interests in the center of the matrix on the intersection
between the dichotomies of individual and communal and subjective and objective.
In conclusion, we posit that continued research into the best practices in ethical decision-making pedagogy and
the thoughtful and thorough examination of ideations that help administrators mediate difficult choices in the
best interests of students would serve to augment the findings of this study. Instrumental in such attempts would
be an extensive examination to understand the societal factors and the educational context in which Canadian
in-school administrators make decisions in the best interests of children, which could be then compared with
contexts in other countries. As education is a provincial responsibility in Canada and systems of education in
provinces and territories differ and are unique in some regard, we suggest that further inquiry to uncover the
effect of educational policies and cultural aspects of schooling in various jurisdictions is necessary.
Furthermore, we emphasize the need for continued research in the area of multiple ethical paradigms, ethical
leadership, and ethical decision-making" among in-school administrators and encourage school leaders to apply
the principle of the best interests of the child by bringing into consideration the commonly taken-for-granted
jurisprudential and ethical meanings and interpretations that are perhaps over-embedded and underconsidered
in the cliché-oriented notion of the best interests of the child.
Acknowledgment
This work was supported by a grant from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada.
References
References
Apple, M.W. (1988). Teachers and texts: A political economy of class and gender relations in education. New
York: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Apple, M.W. (2001). Educating the "right" way: Markets, standards, God, and inequality. New York: Routledge
Falmer.
Apple, M.W. (2003). The State and the Politics of Knowledge. New York: Routledge Falmer.
Bailey, S. (2006). Decision making in acute care: A practical framework supporting the 'best interests' principle.
Nursing Ethics, 13,284-291.
Beck, L.G. (1994). Reclaiming educational administration as a caring profession. New York: Teachers College
Press.
Beckner, W. (2004). Ethics for educational leaders. Boston, MA: Pearson.
Begley, P.T. (2006). Self-knowledge, capacity and sensitivity: Prerequisites to authentic leadership by school
principals. Journal of Educational Administration, 44, 570-589.
Begley, P.T. (Ed.). (1999). Values and educational leadership. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
Begley, P.T., &Zaretsky, L. (2004). Democratic school leadership in Canada's public school systems:
Professional value and social ethic. Journal of Educational Administration, 42, 640655.
Bishop-Yong, N. (2010). The best interests principle in administrative practice: Canadian in-school
administrators' perceptions, definitions and use of the best interests principle. Unpublished master's thesis.
University of Saskatchewan.
Bitensky, S. (1992). Theoretical foundations for a fight to education under the U.S. Constitution: A beginning to
the end of the national education crisis. Northwestern University Law Review 86, 550-642.
23 October 2014 Page 21 of 26 ProQuestBush, T. (1998). The National Professional Qualification for Headship: The key to effective school leadership?
School Leadership and Management, 18, 321-334.
Bush, T. (2008). From management to leadership: Semantic or meaningful change? Educational Management,
Administration and Leadership, 36, 271-288.
Bush, T. (2011). Theories of educational leadership and management (4th ed.). London: Sage.
Campbell, E. (1999). Ethical school leadership: Problems of an elusive role. In P. Begley (Ed.), Values and
educational leadership (pp. 151-163). Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
Capron, A.M. (1982). The competence of children as self-deciders in biomedical interventions. In W. Gaylin &R.
Macklin (Eds.), Who speaks for the child: The problems of proxy consent (pp. 57-114). New York: Plenum
Press.
Clarke, P.T., Heavin, H., &Walker, K.D. (2010). Racist parenting and the best interests of the child: A legal and
ethical analysis. Canadian Journal of Educational Administration and Policy, 109,1-47.
Cranston, N., Ehrich, L. C., &Kimber, M. (2006). Ethical dilemmas: The "bread and butter" of educational
leaders' lives, journal of Educational Administration, 44,106-121.
Cuban, L. (1998). The managerial imperative and the practice of leadership in schools. Albany, NY: SUNY
Press.
Denig, S.J., &Quinn, T. (2001). Ethical dilemmas for school administrators. The High School journal, 84(4), 43-
50.
Department of Justice Canada. (2004). Fact sheet Section 43 of the Criminal Code Corporal Punishment: The
Canadian Foundation for Children, Youth and the Law v. The Attorney General of Canada. Available:
http://canada.justice.gc.ca/en/news/fs/2004/doc_31114.html
Donlevy, Kv &Walker, K. (2011). Working through ethics in education and leadership. Rotterdam, Netherlands:
Sense Publications.
Duignan, P., &Bhindi, N. (1997). Authenticity in leadership: an emerging perspective, journal of Educational
Administration, 35,195-209.
Dworkin, G. (1982). Consent, representation and proxy consent. In W. Gaylin &R. Macklin (Eds.), Who speaks
for the child: The problems of proxy consent (pp. 191-208). New York: Plenum Press.
Evers, C., &Lakomski, G. (1990). Knowing educational administration: Contemporary methodological
controversies in educational administration research. Oxford, UK: Pergamon Press.
Foster, W. (1986). Paradigms and promises: New approaches to educational administration. Buffalo, NY:
Prometheus Books.
Foucault, M. (1983). On the genealogy of ethics: an overview of work in progress. In H. L. Dreyfus &P. Rabinow
(Eds.), Michel Foucault: Beyond structuralism and hermeneutics (2nd ed., pp. 229-252). Chicago, IL: University
of Chicago Press.
Freire, P. (1970). Pedagogy of the oppressed (M.B. Ramos, Trans.). New York: Continuum.
Frick, W. (2006). An empirical investigation of secondary principals' perspectives on "the best interests of the
students" as a viable professional ethic for educational leadership. Unpublished doctoral dissertation,
Pennsylvania State University.
Furman, G.C. (2004). The ethic of community. Journal of Educational Administration, 42,215-235.
Gathercoal, F. (1991). judicious discipline (2nd ed.). Davis, CA: Caddo Gap Press.
Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Giroux, H.A. (1994). Educational leadership and school administrators: Rethinking the meaning of democratic
public culture. In T. Mulkeen, N.H. Cambron-McCabe &B. Anderson (Eds.), Democratic leadership: The
changing context of administrative preparation (pp. 31-47). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Greenfield, W. (2004). Moral leadership in schools, journal of Educational Administration, 42, 174-196.
Hallinger, P. (2003). Reshaping the landscape of school leadership: A global perspective. Lisse, Netherlands:
23 October 2014 Page 22 of 26 ProQuestSwets and Zeitlinger.
Hodgkinson, C. (1978). Towards a philosophy of administration. New York: St. Martin's Press.
Hodgkinson, C. (1991). Educational Leadership: the moral art. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
Hoyle, E., &Wallace, M. (2005). Educational leadership: Ambiguity, professionals, and managerialism. London:
Sage.
Johansson, O. (2004). A democratic, learning and communicative leadership. Journal of Educational
Administration, 42, 697-707.
Jonsen, A. (1968). Responsibility in modern religious ethics. Washington, DC: Corpus Books.
Katz, M.S., Noddings, Ν., &Strike, K. (Eds.). (1999). Justice and caring: The search for common ground in
education. New York: Teachers College Press.
Kimbrough, R.B. (1985). Current study for educational leader. Arlington, VA: American Association of School
Administrators.
Kopelman, L.M. (1997). The best-interests standard as a threshold, ideal, and standard of reasonableness.
Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 22, 271-289.
Langlois, L. (2004). Responding ethically: Complex decision-making by school district superintendents.
International Studies in Educational Administration and Management, 32(2), 78-93.
Langlois, L. (2008). Anatomie d'un leadership éthique. Quebec, QC: Université Laval.
Langlois, L., &Lapointe, C. (2007). Ethical leadership in Canadian school organizations: Tensions and
possibilities. Educational Management Administration &Leadership, 35, 247-260. doi: DOI:
10.1177/1741143207075391
Langlois, L., &Starratt, R. J. (2001). Identification of superintendent and school commissioners' ethical
perspective: A case study and overlapping ethical framework: data talking to the model. Paper presented at the
Conference on Ethics and Leadership, Charlotteville, VA.
Lichtman, M. (2010). Qualitative research in education: A user's guide. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
MacMillan, J.H., &Schumacher, S. (2006). Research in education: Evidence-based inquiry. Boston, MA:
Pearson.
Noddings, N. (1984). Feminine approach to ethics and moral education. Berkeley, CA: University of California
Press.
Noddings, N. (1999). Care, justice, and equity. In M.S. Katz, N. Noddings, &K.A. Strike (Eds.), Justice and
caring: The search for common ground in education (pp. 7-20). New York: Teachers College Press.
Noddings, N. (2002). Educating moral people: A caring alternative to character education. New York: Teachers
College Press.
Noddings, N. (Ed.). (2005). The challenge to care in schools: An alternative approach to education (2nd ed.).
New York: Teachers College Press.
Normore, A.H. (2004). Ethics and values in leadership preparation programs: Finding the north star in the dust
storm. Values and Ethics in Educational Administration, 2(2), 1-8.
Northouse, P.G. (2013). Leadership (6th ed.). London: Sage.
Purpel, D.E. (2004). Reflections on the moral and spiritual crisis in education. New York: Peter Lang.
Rebore, R.W. (2001). The ethics of educational leadership. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Merrill Prentice Hall.
Rucinski, A.D., &Bauch, P.A. (2006). Reflective, ethical, and moral constructs in educational leadership
preparation: Effects on graduates' practices. Journal ofEducational Administration, 44, 487-508.
Selznick, P. (1984). Leadership in administration: A sociological approach. San Francisco, CA: Harper Row.
Sergiovanni, T.J. (1992). Moral leadership: Getting to the heart of school improvement. San Francisco, CA:
Jossey-Bass.
Sernak, K. (1998). School leadership: Balancing power with caring. New York: Teachers College Press.
Shapiro, J. P. (2006). Ethical decision making in turbulent time: bridging theory with practice to prepare
23 October 2014 Page 23 of 26 ProQuestauthentic educational leaders. Values and Ethics in Educational Administration, 4(2), 1-8.
Shapiro, J.P., &Gross, S. (2008). Ethical leadership in turbulent times: (Re)Solving moral dilemmas. New York:
Erlbaum.
Shapiro, J.P., &Hassinger, R.E. (2007). Using case studies of ethical dilemmas for the development of moral
literacy: Towards educating for social justice. Journal of Educational Administration, 45, 451-470.
Shapiro, J.P., &Stefkovich, J.A. (2001a). Ethical leadership and decision making in education: Applying
theoretical perspectives to complex dilemmas. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Shapiro, J.P., &Stefkovich, J.A. (2001b). Response of the review of ethical leadership and decision making in
education. British Journal of Educational Psychology, 71,364.
Shapiro, J.P., &Stefkovich, J.A. (2005). Ethical leadership and decision making in education: Applying
theoretical perspectives to complex dilemmas (2nd ed.). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Shapiro, J.P., &Stefkovich, J.A. (Eds.). (2011). Ethical leadership and decision making in education: Applying
theoretical perspectives to complex dilemmas (3rd ed.). New York: Routledge.
Smith, S. (1998). A child's best interests: A commentary on "jurisprudential and ethical perspectives on the best
interests of children" by Keith Walker. Interchange, 29(3), 309-316.
Starratt, R.J. (1991). Building an ethical school: A theory for practice in educational leadership. Educational
Administration Quarterly, 27,185-202.
Starratt, R.J. (1994). Building an ethical school: A practical response to the moral crisis in schools. London:
Falmer Press.
Starratt, R.J. (2003). Centering educational administration: Cultivating meaning, community, responsibility.
Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Starratt, R.J. (2004). Ethical leadership. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Starratt, R.J. (2005). Responsible leadership. Educational Forum, 69(2), 124-133.
Starratt, R.J. (2010). Developing successful leadership. In B. Davies &M. Brundrett (Eds.), Studies in
educational leadership (vol. 11, pp. 27-37). Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer.
Stefkovich, J.A. (2006). Best interests of the student: Applying ethical constructs to legal cases in education.
Mahwah, NJ: Earlbaum.
Stefkovich, J.A., &Begley, P. (2007). Ethical school leadership: Defining the best interests of students.
Educational Management, Administration, &Leadership, 35, 205-224.
Stefkovich, J.A., &O'Brien, M. (2004). Best interests of the student: An ethical model. Journal of Educational
Administration, 42, 197-214.
Stefkovich, J.A., &Shapiro, J.P. (2003). Deconstructing communities: Educational leaders and their ethical
decision-making processes. In P. Begley &O. Johansson (Eds.), The ethical dimensions of school leadership
(pp. 89-106). Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer Academic.
Strike, K., Haller, E., &Soltis, J. (1988). The ethics of school administration. New York: Teachers College Press.
Tirri, K. (1999). Teachers' perceptions of moral dilemmas at school, journal of Mora! Education, 28(1), 31-47.
Tirri, K., &Husu, J. (2002). Care and responsibility in 'the best interest of the child': Relational voices of ethical
dilemmas in teaching. Teachers and Teaching: Theory and practice, 8(1), 65-80.
Vojak, C. (2003). Mozert v. Hawkins: A look at self-knowledge and the best interests of the child. Educational
Theory, 53,401-418.
Walker, K. (1991). Theory to practice: Ethics in policy research and development. In R. Reilly &C. Lautar (Eds.),
Policy research and development in Canadian education (pp. 73-99). Calgary, AB: University of Calgary Press.
Walker, K. (1995). A principled look at 'the best interests of the children'. Canadian School Executive, 15(5), 3-
8.
Walker, K. (1998a). Jurisprudential and ethical perspectives on "the best interests of children." interchange,
29(3), 287-308. doi: 10.1023/a:1007561315049
23 October 2014 Page 24 of 26 ProQuestWalker, K. (1998b). Response to Dr. Stephen Smith. Interchange, 29(3), 317-326.
Walker, K., &Donlevy, K. (2006). Reconsidering ethical relativism. Journal of School Leadership, 16, 216-239.
Walker, Κ., &Donlevy, K. (2009). The four ethical commitments in educational administration. Journal of
Educational Thought, 43,109-131.
Willower, D.J. (1999). Work on values in educational administration: some observations. Paper presented at the
annual meeting of the University Council for Educational Administration Center for the Study of Ethics and
Leadership, Charlottesville, VA.
AuthorAffiliation
Keith Walker
University of Saskatchewan
Benjamin Kutsyuruba
Queen's University
Nicola Bishop-Yong
Westmount Community School, Saskatoon
AuthorAffiliation
Keith Walker, Professor, University of Saskatchewan, (Department of Educational Administration &Johnson
Shoyama Graduate School of Public Policy), keith.walker@usask.ca
Benjamin Kutsyuruba, Assistant Professor, Queen's University, (Faculty of Education),
ben.kutsyuruba@queensu.ca
Nicola Bishop-Yong, Principal, Westmount Community School, (Saskatoon Public School Division),
bishopn@spsd.sk.ca
Subject: Studies; School principals; Educational leadership; Professional ethics; Decision making;
Location: Canada
Publication title: EAF Journal
Volume: 22
Issue: 2
Pages: 27-I
Number of pages: 35
Publication year: 2011
Publication date: 2011
Year: 2011
Publisher: Journal of Educational Administration and Foundations
Place of publication: Winnipeg
Country of publication: Canada
Publication subject: Education--School Organization And Administration
ISSN: 08313318
Source type: Scholarly Journals
Language of publication: English
Document type: Feature
23 October 2014 Page 25 of 26 ProQuestDocument feature: Tables Charts References
ProQuest document ID: 1353572711
Document URL: http://search.proquest.com/docview/1353572711?accountid=25704
Copyright: Copyright Journal of Educational Administration and Foundations 2011
Last updated: 2013-12-09
Database: ProQuest Education Journals
_______________________________________________________________
Contact ProQuest
Copyright 2014 ProQuest LLC. All rights reserved. - Terms and Conditions
23 October 2014 Page 26 of 26 ProQuest
_______________________________________________________________
Report Information from ProQuest
23 October 2014 15:47
_______________________________________________________________
23 October 2014 ProQuestTable of contents
1. The Principle of Best Interests of Students in the Principalship................................................................... 1
23 October 2014 ii ProQuestDocument 1 of 1
The Principle of Best Interests of Students in the Principalship
Author: Walker, Keith; Kutsyuruba, Benjamin; Bishop-Yong, Nicola
ProQuest document link
Abstract (Abstract): Analyses of the data revealed that the notion of the best interests of the student(s) was
broadly conceptualized and defined in three major categories of thought: best interests as core good, best
interests as good pedagogy, and best interests as comprehensive good. Most respondents identified with a
definition of best interests as a core good. The best interests of students were regularly described as the core or
center of decision-making and the heart of educators' work. One respondent noted, "I would ask staff members
to always remember why we teach-to educate students. They are our priority." It was evident that the
respondents mitigated decisions of best interests by placing the students at the heart of decision-making, or as
one respondent articulated, "We need to see to their needs ahead of our own." Prevalently, respondents
defined best interests as the why of their work and why they entered teaching. Respondents identified an ethical
duty and responsibility toward providing students with the best possible care and attention including decisions
on their behalf. This sense of service responsibility prevailed that: "Students are our client and we have a
responsibility to our students" and that an agreed central purpose of education, best interests, should be "to
serve students." Finally, respondents defined best interests as the best outcome or as a positive benefit.
Decision-making in this manner was depicted as those decisions that led to students' development,
advancement, and growth. One comment encapsulates this point: "What the phrase [best interest] means to me
is that decisions are made from the perspective of providing the best possible outcome for that child."
When describing best interests as good pedagogy, principals used concepts and phrases like learning,
achievement, learning environment, and pedagogy. The best-interests principle was described as a means to
an end. In the view of some respondents, the central purpose or paramount reason for education was students'
learning as indicated in the following responses: "Our central purpose is student learning. I prefer to define 'best
interests' in the context of good pedagogy," and "I would explain it by saying that the paramount reason we are
in business is to advance student learning. If the decision advances student learning, then it is in the best
interest of the student." Decisions of best interests were identified by the respondents as those that "supported]
student learning [and] achievement in a safe and caring learning environment" or enabled students to "flourish
in an environment that is safe and productive to learning." In addition, the respondents defined decisions of best
interests as "interests that [led] to growth through learning opportunities" and higher achievement."
The matrix represents the arguments of several theorists on best interests such as [Stephen Smith] (1998),
Capron (1982), Walker (1998a) and [Shapiro, J.P.] and Stefkovich (2002b) along the intersecting dichotomies.
Smith, like the judiciary, was concerned with the child in his critique of best interests per the educational leader.
According to Smith, there may be "no singular right, good, or virtuous pattern for all children," yet there may be
a singularly right response for the single child and what fundamentally determines the measure of help given the
child is the moral agency of "people [who] are in better positions relative to particular children than others" (p.
309). Similarly, Shapiro and Stefkovich and Stefkovich (2006) centered their research on assisting those in
"better positions"-in-school administrators-to make ethical decisions in the best interests of the student. The
underlying assumpFi tion is that if the individual is treated with fairness, justice, and caring, then a strong
message is sent to all students that they will be afforded justice and caring and that they should treat others
similarly ([Stefkovich, J.A.]). However, unlike Smith's assessment, Shapiro and Stefkovich appeared to hold the
position of whose interests, individual or collective, in a balance. Dworkin (1982) identified that the struggle for
balancing the interests of the individual and the communal lies in terms of not only value conflicts, but also time
conflicts. Writing about political representatives, he suggests that they are asked to balance the interests and
23 October 2014 Page 1 of 26 ProQuestdesires of some against those of others and may have to consider the interests of current generations against
the needs or interests of future generations. Once again, the nature of interests is relational.
Full text: Headnote
The best-interests principle is a widely used ethical, legal, and social basis for making policy and decisions
involving children. This article provides an overview of the state of the conversation about the best interests of
students and a recent study of the concept as it was understood and used by school principals. The purpose of
this research was to examine the best-interests principle through an investigation of theory, practice, and
professional praxis and thus to identify the common use and understanding of the best-interests principle in
Canadian in-school administrative practice. We discuss the moral nature of educational leadership through a
multidimensional ethical framework that comprises ethics of justice, care, critique, community, and profession.
Research methodology consisted of a structured survey that included both closed attitudinal and open-ended
questions. The findings revealed a compelling image of the best-interests principle in educational administrative
practice, emphasized the significance of the multi-ethical paradigms in decision-making, and positioned in-
school administrators vis àvis best interests on the matrix at the intersection of two dichotomies: a focus of
interest (individual-student or the communal-students) and a methodology of deciding-(subjective-case by case
or objective-criteria-based).
The best-interests principle is a widely used ethical, legal, and social construct for mediating making policy and
decisions involving children (Kopelman, 1997). As such, the applications of the principle abound in legal,
medical, and educational contexts where determinations are made on behalf of children. The construct
represents the guiding criterion for legal disputes about custody and access (Department of Justice Canada,
2004). In addition, this notion is a common reference point used in quasi-medical and medical contexts (Bailey,
2006; Kopelman). In educational contexts, the best-interests principle has received increased attention in the
mitigation of ethical and legal decision-making (Cranston, Ehrich, &Kimber, 2006; Frick, 2006; Shapiro
&Stefkovich, 2001a; Stefkovich &Begley, 2007; Stefkovich &O'Brien, 2004; Tirri, 1999; Tirri &Husu, 2002;
Walker, 1995,1998a)
The best interests of students has become a common shibboleth of "enormous potential to direct and to
measure goodness, Tightness, and appropriateness of policy and practice" (Walker, 1995, p. 5) for educators,
policymakers, and legal adjudicators. The phrase is a first source of demarcation for educators who will often
evoke the phrase to show their colors. As such, it is the common proxy for saying, "All that we do and say in
education ought to be in the stewardship of our compelling moral purpose to support the healthy growth and
development of children and youth." Often the phrase is used as a shorthand expression of the taken-for-
granted summum bonum (the greatest good) that must be preserved in the outworking of all or any educational
policy decisions; as in "We must not transgress the best interests of the students with this new policy." Also, of
course, in the reading of almost any legal case dealing with the interests of the child or the competing interests
of adults where children are involved, one witnesses the use of the construct of best interests as a hinge
(cardinal) principle against which the warrants of conflicting perspectives must be measured before resolving
decisions may be made. Much best-interests discourse appears inside and around educational organizations
(i.e., staff rooms, classrooms, schools, and school systems), in the work of education policy agents, and in
societal institutions (governments and judicial bodies). However, although the concept is present in the parlance
of educational communities, we argue that there is a lack of meaningful attention and exegesis in proportion to
its evocative use.
Although work has been done to theorize best interests as a guiding principle in ethical leadership and decision-
making in education, only a small number of empirical studies have been conducted, and qualitative research
on the perceptions of this principle by educational leaders has been inconclusive (Frick, 2006; Shapiro
&Stefkovich, 2001a, 2001b; Stefkovich, 2006; Walker, 1995). Despite attempts to provide a rigorous definition,
the research reveals that best interests is used broadly and interpreted in multiple ways. Consequently, the
23 October 2014 Page 2 of 26 ProQuest"potent phrase" (Walker, 1998a), often used as justification and rationalization for administrative decisions,
requires critical examination. Of course, difficult and "wicked" problems do not rely on rational, traditional, or
bureaucratic policy and decision-making processes for resolution, but we would still advocate a view that the
use of in the best interests of the student(s) by school principals requires mapping and charting. It is imperative
for in-school administrators to grapple with the complexities of applying the best-interests principle, both ethical
and jurisprudential. Our effort here is not to simplify the work of school leaders, but to begin to unpack and
make sense of a concept that may be espoused without appreciation of either the substantive construct or the
context complexities. For as Walker (1995) wrote, "the more committed and competent we are in finding the
ethical courage to do what is clearly in the best interests of children, the better we will serve the children of our
schools" (p. 8). Studies on the best-interests principle represent a significant opportunity to examine various
dimensions of ethical leadership. Although the child, children, the student, or the students should not be
essentialized or homogenized, a critical perspective of these central constructs is beyond the scope of this
article.
Here we provide an overview of the state of the conversation about the best interests of students and report on
a recent study that focused on the concept as it was understood and used by school principals. The purpose of
this research was to examine the best-interests principle through an investigation of theory, practice, and
professional praxis, and thus to identify the common use and understandings of the best-interests principle in
Canadian in-school administrative practice. In the following sections, we begin the discussion of the moral
nature of educational leadership through a multidimensional ethical framework comprising ethics of justice,
care, critique, community, and profession, together with jurisprudential and ethical decision-making
perspectives. We then describe and discuss the perceptions of Canadian principals regarding the notion of best
interests of students and ethical dilemmas in administrative decision-making. The article concludes with an
interpretative matrix to describe principals' perspectives and the challenges for ongoing research related to this
persistently important concept.
Ethical Frameworks and Educational Leaders' Pursuit of Students' Best Interests
Although principalship has historically been framed within the notions of administration or management, only
recently has leadership overtaken them as the main descriptor for what is entailed in running and proving public
service organizations (Bush, 2008; Hoyle &Wallace, 2005; Selznick, 1984). Leadership is often linked with
change, vision, values, or purpose, whereas management and administration are related to maintenance,
implementation, or technical issues (Bush, 1998; Cuban, 1998), However, both dimensions of organizational
activity are present and important in the role of school administrators (Bush, 2011). As Hallinger (2003) argued,
leadership perspective on the role of the principal does not diminish the principal's managerial role. Moreover,
Starratt (2004) cautioned about presenting and interpreting issues that school leaders face primarily as
technical, rationalizable problems resolvable by technical, rational solutions, and not surfacing the human, civic,
and moral challenges nested in many of these problems. Similarly, Sergiovanni (1992) implies that technical
expertise without a moral compass is inadequate for the task, as is a moral compass without technical
expertise.
The assertion that educational leadership is a fundamentally moral endeavor has been developed over many
years by numerous scholars (Begley, 1999; Furman, 2004; Greenfield, 2004; Hodgkinson, 1991; Johansson,
2004; Langlois, 2008; Sernak, 1998; Starratt, 1994). A number of theoretical foundations for understanding
ethical leadership have been developed by Nod-dings (1984), Duignan and Bhindi (1997), Strike, Haller, and
Soltis (1988), Kimbrough (1985), Sergiovanni, and Starratt (1991, 2004). Writing on the philosophy of
administration 20 years ago, Hodgkinson encapsulated the "then modern state" of educational leadership when
he termed it "especially difficult, especially challenging and especially moral" and said that it was in essence,
"philosophy-in-action" (pp. 63, 115) We assert that this state remains as Hodgkinson described it: administration
is a moral art that points to our need for wisdom, and "leadership is always a function of value and of
23 October 2014 Page 3 of 26 ProQuestcommitment to organizational value or purpose (p. 27). It is beyond the scope of this article to explicate and
exegete the axiological, epistemological, and ontological presuppositions for this wide-ranging collection of
educational scholars. This has been done elsewhere (Evers &Lakomski, 1990; Hodgkinson, 1978). Nor do we
delve into specific schools or doctrines of ethics as has been done in earlier works (Donlevy &Walker, 2011;
Walker, 1991; Walker &Donlevy, 2006, 2009).
Campbell (1999) observed that central to much of the ethical leadership literature is that "educational leaders
must develop and articulate a much greater awareness of the ethical significance of their actions and
decisions." (p. 152). As Starratt (1991) suggested, ultimately, "educational leaders have a moral responsibility to
be proactive about creating an ethical environment for the conduct of education" (p. 187). In his review of
comparative systems of ethics, Rebore (2001) evoked three justifications for the relevance of ethics in
educational leadership: (a) ethics not only provide a framework for decision-making, but also require reflection
on values; (b) ethics support disciplined ways of thinking; and (c) ethical analysis offers a unique response to
the demands of leadership. Whereas typical leadership approaches, instructional or managerial, might answer
the questions of how and what, a well-developed sense and competence in ethical leadership can help answer
the question of why (Rebore).
In their examination of the daily practices of school administrators, researchers (Langlois, 2004; Langlois
&Starratt, 2001) discovered that certain situations were increasingly challenging for them in terms of how they
justified their decisions and in the difficulty that they experienced in understanding the ethical issues in their
practice. Similarly, Beckner (2004) posited that to many administrators, philosophy and ethics seem rather far
removed from the everyday challenges of educational leadership and management, and they tend to rely more
on experience and personal judgment. However, the influence dimension of leadership requires the leaders to
have an effect on the lives of those being led, so making a change in other people carries with it an enormous
ethical burden and responsibility (Northouse, 2013). Moreover, as Stefkovich (2006) noted,
Ethics should guide school leaders' decision making, [so] that there can be common ground even in
multicultural, pluralistic society, and that, rather than impose their own values on students and teachers, school
leaders should strive to reach a higher moral ground in making decisions, (p. 4)
Applied ethics help educational leadership to move from bureaucratic systems and control toward empowering
teachers and participation in making decisions (Rucinski &Bauch, 2006). Ethical considerations enlarge and
enrich the language and frames of deliberation for school leaders with respect to their professional and moral
purpose, obligations, and agency on behalf of students and other stakeholders. In this article, we position the
best interests of students as an important criterion for ethical deliberation and determinations. A delimitation of
this study is that its context and the selection of literature cited draws primarily on English-speaking,
Commonwealth, and United States contexts. Our interest is to provoke enhanced dialogical competence,
particularly with respect to ethical issues and decisions in schools. Given these assertions, what part do the
interests of students or the best interests of children have in the conduct of education and the ethical
adjudication work of school principals?
Best Interests of Students
The concept of the best interests of the students is most usefully understood in the context of our vision of what
might constitute an ethical framework for those working with children and youth in the educational sector.
Scholars have produced and elaborated multidimensional ethical frameworks (Begley, 2006; Furman, 2004;
Katz, Noddings, &Strike, 1999; Shapiro &Gross, 2008; Shapiro &Hassinger, 2007; Shapiro &Stefkovich, 2001b;
Starratt, 1994; Stefkovich, 2006) that envisage and conceptualize the effect of diverse ethical perspectives on
educational leaders. Shapiro and Hassinger call these perspectives paradigms.
Developed in response to the complex ethical challenges facing contemporary society, the approaches of ethic
of justice, ethic of care, ethic of critique (Starratt, 1994), ethic of profession (Shapiro &Stefkovich, 2001b), and
ethic of community (Furman, 2004) may be drawn together by principals to create an integrated framework for
23 October 2014 Page 4 of 26 ProQuestethical practice. As Starratt noted, the interpénétration of each of these ethical and interpretative themes is
necessary for the fully developed moral person, fully developed human society, and we would add, the agentic
leader. We contend that the ethics described below should not be set in opposition to one another, but viewed
as collectively comprising an ethics system with a web of concepts and applications.
Ethic of Justice
Fairness or equal treatment is the core value underlying an ethic of justice. It focuses on rights and law, as
"society must establish rules that are fair to all and then live by those rules" (Noddings, 1999, p. 8). Starratt
(1994) conceived the ethic of justice as requiring that we "govern ourselves by observing justice" and
henceforth "treat each other according to some standard of justice" (p. 49), which is uniformly applied to all
relationships. For Starratt, this type of ethic emanates from two schools of thought: one, represented by Thomas
Hobbes and John Rawls, advocated for the individual as the primary human reality, independent of social
relationships and logically prior to society who engages in a social contract with the community; and the second,
represented to various degrees by Aristotle, Rousseau, Hegel, Marx, and Dewey, placed the society as the prior
reality in which the individual develops. Although these philosophers came from diverse philosophical traditions
and in some cases diametrically opposed perspectives, they viewed ethics as grounded in practice in the
community. In this regard, the person living in society learns the lessons of morality through experience; and
participation in the life of the community teaches the individual how to think of his or her own behavior in terms
of the larger common good of the community. Starratt (2003) contended that an ethic of justice, especially when
focused on the issues of governance in a school setting, can encompass both understandings: "justice
understood as individual choice to act justly and justice understood as the community's choice to direct or
govern its actions justly" (p. 144).
Denig and Quinn (2001) state that this ethic perceives ethical decision-making as rational, logical, systemic, and
enhanced by universal principles. As such, Shapiro and Hassinger (2007) suggest that this ethic leads in-school
administrators to questions such as: Is there a law, right, or policy that would be appropriate for resolving a
particular ethical dilemma? Why is this law, right, or policy the correct one for this particular case? Does this law
or policy serve our deliberations or adjudication of the best interests of the students? How should the law, right,
or policy be implemented such that students' best interests are served? In summary, the ethic of justice focuses
on rights, law, and policies and concepts such as fairness, equality, and individual freedom.
Ethic of Care
The ethic and concept of care are often described as a relation based on mutual agreement, loyalty, or
alignment. Starratt (1994) denoted that an ethic of care requires "fidelity to persons" and absolute regard and
love. It is concerned less with fairness and more with caring for individuals as unique persons. This ethic is
rooted in the work of Gilligan's (1982) analysis of Kohlberg's moral development and subsequent writers like
Noddings (1984, 2005) and Beck (1994). Its relational nature is reflected in Beck's contention that "the
communal relationships between people mean that the welfare of each is inextricably related to the welfare of
others ... such that caring for others is, in fact, caring for oneself" (p. 20). Rucinski and Bauch (2006) called for
in-school administrators to be grounded in the ethic of care and in belief in the sacredness of human
relationships and the good of human beings in the school organization.
Noddings (2005) and Sergiovanni (1992) have challenged the status of the ethic of justice as dominant among
ethical paradigms in education and law and have called for more attention to concepts such as loyalty, trust,
and empowerment. However, whereas theoretical opposition to the dominance of the ethic of justice advances
theoretical understandings and provides space for the use of the ethic of care, academics routinely call for the
two ethics to be balanced (Sernak, 1998; Shapiro &Hassinger, 2007; Stefkovich, 2006). Stefkovich identified
three factors intrinsic to this concept:
1. Understanding self both as separate from and in relation to community,
2. Building a just and democratic pluralistic school community; and
23 October 2014 Page 5 of 26 ProQuest3. Experiencing personal freedom in order to fully function in a community. (p. 11)
The relationship between the ethic of care and best interests is profound in the light of Rucinski and Bauch's
(2006) call for educational leaders to be grounded in the ethic of care and in belief in the sacredness of human
relationships and the good of human beings in the school organization. Similarly, Shapiro and Hassinger (2007)
suggested that this ethic asks in-school administrators to consider the consequences of their decisions and
actions by taking into account questions such as: Who will benefit from what I decide? Who will be hurt by my
actions? What are the long-term effects of a decision I make today? And if I am helped by someone now, what
should I do in the future about giving back to this individual or to society in general? In summary, the ethic of
care is rooted in relationship-building, trust in, and compassion for others.
Ethic of Critique
The ethic of critique deals with questions of social justice and human dignity and the morality of social and
political resistance (Starratt, 2003). It is aimed at awakening our attention to the inequities found in schools and
in society and represents a challenge to the status quo in order to give a voice to the marginalized (Rucinski
&Bauch, 2006; Stefkovich, 2006). This ethic recognizes that no social arrangement is neutral. Every social
arrangement, no matter how it presents itself, is artificial (Starratt, 1994). Arrangements are usually structured to
benefit some segments of society at the expense of others, and hence the ethical challenge is to make these
social arrangements more responsive to the human and social rights of all citizens, especially the marginalized
and "the least among us." The challenge for educational leaders is to expose and confront the tough questions
of social class, race, gender, and so forth. This ethic requires educators to deal with the hard questions in areas
of difference including: Who makes the laws, rules, or policies? Who benefits from these laws, rules, or
policies? Who has the power? Who are the silenced voices (Shapiro &Hassinger, 2007)? And who says this or
that is an action, accommodation, affordance, or appropriation in the best interests of students? Applying the
ethic of critique may require confronting some entrenched assumptions about the assumed legitimacy of the
status quo and the risk of standing up to superiors who support, even by their own passivity, the status quo
(Starratt, 2010).
The ethic of critique has been elaborated by critical theorists and activists, as well as critical pedagogy theorists
who analyze social class and inequities (Apple, 1988, 2001, 2003; Foucault, 1983; Freire, 1970; Giroux, 1994;
Purpel, 2004; Shapiro, 2006). In this respect, the ethic of critique provides a "discourse in expanding basic
human rights" (Shapiro &Stefkovich, 2001b, p. 14) and the basis for moving from discourse to action. Such a
critique and posture leads to the development of options related to important concepts such as oppression,
power, culture, privilege, authority, voice, language empowerment, and in particular, social justice. In summary,
the ethic of critique is typified by a critical inquiry of differences.
Ethic of Community
Furman (2004) suggested that increased attention be given in the ethics literature to collaborative work and
communal processes necessary to build an ethical school and to achieve the moral purpose of schooling in the
21st century. Furthermore, Furman lamented that ethical frames often do little to pull our thinking beyond the
mindset so entrenched in our Western society of the individual as leader and moral agent. Defined as "the
moral responsibility to engage in communal processes" (p. 215), an ethic of community envisages
administrators, teachers, school staff members, students, parents, and other community members engaging in
communal processes as they pursue the moral purposes of schooling. Thus an ethic of community privileges
the communal over the individual as moral agent. The shift of the locus of moral agency to the community as a
whole is represented as preeminent in relation to the other ethical paradigms. According to Furman, the ethic of
community captures the centrality of this need for communal processes as the ethics of justice, critique, and
care (Starratt, 1994) and the profession (Shapiro &Stefkovich, 2001b) do not. We might ask what we think are
the alternative courses of action that collectively provide for this cohort of students, in this community, given our
values and plural interests. Viewed through the lens of the ethic of community, best interests are community-
23 October 2014 Page 6 of 26 ProQuestminded and pluralistic in nature.
Ethic of Profession
A number of scholars (Beck, 1994; Begley, 1999; Normore, 2004; Shapiro, 2006; Starratt, 2010; Stefkovich,
2006; Willower, 1999) have advocated that school administrators have professional preparation in ethics, and
especially in ethical decision-making. According to Shapiro and Stefkovich (2005), even taken together, the
ethics of justice, critique, and care do not provide an adequate picture of the factors that must be taken into
consideration as leaders strive to make ethical decisions in the context of educational settings. Shapiro and
Stefkovich aptly surmised, "not all those who write about the importance of the study of ethics in educational
administration discuss the needs of children; however, this focus on students is clearly consistent with the
backbone of our profession" (p. 23). They argued that if there were a moral imperative for educational
administration, it would be to serve the best interests of the student and that this ideal would lie at the heart of a
professional paradigm for in-school administrators. Starratt (2004, 2010) argues that an educational leader's
professional ethical responsibility is to promote the good of the practice of the profession, namely, to promote
the good of learning, the good of general education. Shapiro and Hassinger (2007) identify that the lens of the
ethic of the profession to resolve an ethical dilemma raises questions such as, What is in the best interests of
the student? What are the personal and professional codes of an educational leader? What professional
organizations' codes of ethics should be considered in order to best serve the interests of these students? What
does the local community think about this issue? And what is the appropriate way for a professional to act in this
particular situation, based on the standards of practice for the profession?
The ethic of profession takes into account not only the standards of the profession, but also community
standards, the personal and professional codes of an educational leader, and the professional codes of a
number of educational organizations (Shapiro &Stefkovich, 2001a). The integration of personal and professional
codes may lead to a clash of codes that the school leader will need to negotiate. The best interests of the
student is a moral ideal that can be relied on to calm the internal struggle between personal morality, what is
determined as right and good according to the individual, and what an organization and/or the profession
expects, values, and delineates as right and good practice (Frick, 2006). Factors that play in the development of
professional codes may include, but not be limited to, the inclusion of considerations of community standards,
including both the professional community and the community in which the leader works. Stefkovich and
Shapiro (2003) advocate that dialoguing about and in the communities of work to help address the silencing is
especially important to critical theorists. Hence, community is embedded in the model and is not interpreted as a
stand-alone ethic as in Furman's (2004) model. However whether community is viewed as a separate ethic or
part of a larger schema, as positive or negative, its influence on ethical decision-making in schools may be
profound and should not be underestimated (Stefkovich, 2006). Stefkovich summarized that the ethic of
profession asks educational leaders to "to create a dynamic model that places 'the best interests of the student'
as central" (p. 14) and as such is a core moral imperative for educational leaders.
Promoting a Student's Best Interests: Ethical and Jurisprudential Considerations
Of course, ethical decision-making is more easily espoused and intended than it is enacted and implemented. It
is our view that an awareness or consciousness of and language for articulating ethical challenges with respect
to the best interests of students may contribute to better decisions for students. As with earlier explication,
numerous attempts in recent writing on ethical leadership have been made to examine the relationship between
the best-interests principle and decision-making. However, as Clarke et al. (2010) argued, the best interests of
the child test has been criticized for its indeterminacy; simply put, there is no single definition of what is or is not
in the best interests of a child. In the absence of any clear definition of best interests, a guide to determine
factors to be considered in making ethical decisions was developed by Stefkovich (2006) and later elaborated
on by Stefkovich and Begley (2007). This guide for educational leaders in making decisions in the student's best
interest consists of three broadly conceived jurisprudential constructs (by this we mean the understandings from
23 October 2014 Page 7 of 26 ProQuest"regime" law-making and judicial interpretations in case law): rights, responsibility, and respect. These concepts
incorporate Walker's (1998a) claim to ground educational decisions and policies in ethics and jurisprudence.
Relying on context, this conceptualization takes into account students' voices and begins with the assumption
that school officials will engage in active inquiry and self-reflection in order to make decisions that are truly in
the best interests of the student rather than self-serving or merely expedient (Stefkovich &Begley).
Rights are essential to determining a student's best interests and include: rights granted to all human beings as
articulated by philosophers past and present; and universal rights recognized by the United Nations, and
particularly those rights acknowledged under its Convention on the Rights of the Child. The use of the best-
interests construct and approach to decision-making is evident in judicial cases across the Commonwealth
nations, in Europe, and in states associated with the United Nations. In addition, this approach recognizes the
existence of certain fundamental rights as universal despite the fact that some countries seem not to have fully
recognized them in practice (Bitensky, 1992). As a result, caution is warranted when using the word universal to
differentiate ideals from realities and to acknowledge the difference between jurisprudential principle and
alignment of intention to actual behavior and decision-making in educational practice and experience.
Although individual rights are fundamental, they are not unfettered (Stefkovich, 2006). Accordingly, we advocate
an approach that honors the philosophical tradition of accompanying rights with responsibility. Indeed, theorists
past and present from many diverse perspectives consider rights to be incomplete if viewed without
consideration of accompanying responsibilities. Although not based directly on utilitarian ethics, John Stuart
Mill's words on responsibility are viewed as significant: "Everyone who receives the protection of society owes a
return for the benefit, and the fact that living in society renders it indispensable that each should be bound to
observe a certain line of conduct toward the rest" (1978, cited in Stefkovich, 2006, p. 23). Noteworthy is the
differentiation between two major orientations of the term responsibility (Jonsen, 1968): the ex post
responsibility of attribution (i.e., holding responsibility for the commission of an act), and the ex ante
responsibility of appropriation (i.e., antecedent responsibility on the event or activity). Influenced by Locke,
Rousseau, and Kant, contemporary scholars have connected ethical decision-making with the latter orientation
to responsibility that one has in making moral choices. This pattern of thinking about responsibility is concerned
with a more general sense of expectations that in a given role, one will perform as a morally responsible agent
(Starratt, 2004). Inclusion of responsibility in the conceptualization of the best interests of students is supported
by Starratt (2005), Gilligan (1982), and Noddings (2002), each of whom recognized the concepts of authentic
self and empathy.
The concept of respect has been applied to ethics across many disciplines and arises in each of the five ethics
that we delineate in this article. There is no agreement as to a central definition, and philosophers often
conceptualize respect through the Golden Rule. Most often the respect-of-persons doctrine is equated with the
work of Kant, who proffered respect for persons as central to moral theory. In the light of an array of definitions
of respect, Stefkovich (2006) offered Kant's placement of respect in moral theory as a foundation to its inclusion
in her model, and as such it means to treat others never as a means to ends, but as ends. The best-interests
model conceptualizes respect as a cornerstone of ethical behavior that requires positive, mutual interactions
between individuals. Stefkovich envisaged respect as including equity, equality, tolerance, self-respect,
acceptance, and "a commitment to finding common ground in an increasingly multicultural, pluralistic society"
(p. 26).
The ethics and jurisprudential literature impart a continued concern with the nature of the principle and the
process of determining best interests, resulting in continual reflection and critique. Stefkovich's (2006) best-
interests model sought to provide a jurisprudentially and ethically defensible expression of what is in a student's
best interests and to assist educational leaders in understanding that self-reflection, open-mindedness, and
sensitivity are necessary qualities and that making ethically sound decisions profoundly influences others' lives
(Frick, 2006). Consequently, the "myriad of considerations" that are imposed in resolutions of best interests
23 October 2014 Page 8 of 26 ProQuestimpose a great deal of pressure on decision-makers to use their ethical discretion and dialogical competence
(Walker, 1998a, p. 293). Educators are best informed as to the extent and depth of best interests through
considerations of ethical and jurisprudential interpretations.
Educational leaders increasingly deal with questions about who holds the overriding authority in decisions about
particular children. Walker (1998a) claimed that it may be wise to exchange the question "What is best for these
children?" with the question "Who should decide what is best for these children?" Walker (1998b) articulated
this modern conundrum when he wrote, "Sometimes parents, educational professionals, special interests
groups, state representatives of justice, education and social services all vie for legal position and pre-
eminence" (p. 321). He contended that educational leaders were well positioned to help negotiate among
various stakeholders and indeed state that it is the core responsibility of educational leaders to work with their
collaborators to mediate competing interests and for "collaborative processes to bring grassroots expertise to
bear on decisions that make a difference for children" (p. 320). Hodgkinson (1991) rather famously argued that
educational administration finds itself in a rather special-case position among administrative professions:
Its leaders find themselves in what might be called an arena of ethical excitement-often politicized but always
humane, always intimately connected to the evolution of society, sometimes invested with the Type I values of
the culture. Besides, education is both an institution in the sociological sense and a vested interest in the
political science sense. It embodies a heritage of value, on the one hand, and is a massive industry on the
other, in which social, economic, and political forces are locked together in a complex equilibrium of power, (p.
164)
He concluded that all these factors call for extraordinary value sensitivity on the part of educational leaders.
Beyond the extant literature on the best interests of students, just how do the principals as leaders understand
and make use in practice of the concept of the best interests of students? This was the question that we sought
to explore in the study described below.
Methodology
Our purpose for the research was to examine the best-interests principle through an investigation of theory,
practice, and professional praxis and thus to identify the common use and understanding of the best-interests
principle in Canadian in-school administrative practice. This study is a subset of an extensive examination of the
Canadian school principals' perceptions of their moral agency, ethical problems, challenges, pressures, and
influences at work and grounds for their ethical decision-making and recovering of trust in schools. This article
selectively deals with the participants' perceptions of the principle of best interests of children/students as it
applied to their principalship. Five research questions guided the study: How do in-school administrators define
and use best interests? In what circumstances do in-school administrators use best interests? What factors
influence their decisions of best interest? How do in-school administrators make determinations of best
interests? and What is the extent of in-school administrators' conceptualization of best interests?
The target population for this study included Canadian in-school administrators. We asked a stratified sample of
780 in-school administrators to participate in the survey. The participants were identified by an analysis of
multiple educational databases at the national, provincial, and divisional levels. Of the total number of surveys
distributed (N=780), 17% or 132 in-school administrators chose to participate in the study. Although the sample
represented all Canadian provinces and territories, we note that three of the 13 jurisdictions had a
disproportionately higher response rate. The participants were all practicing in-school administrators throughout
Canada.
As a primary data-collection tool for this study, we administered a survey in both mail-out and on-line forms. The
best interests questionnaire, consisting of 14 closed- and open-ended questions, was embedded in a larger
study survey on moral agency and trust that fielded five questionnaires: two online versions and three mailed
versions. Embedded into the online versions and two of the three mailed versions, the survey was distributed to
a stratified sample of in-school administrators across Canada. We developed items for the instrument based on
23 October 2014 Page 9 of 26 ProQuestrecommendations from principals and questions raised in the literature. To check for content validity, we field-
tested the survey with a group of principals and a panel of experts reviewed it before distribution.
In this study, the quantitative and qualitative data were not prioritized. Instead, we collected quantitative and
qualitative data, weighted them equally, and analyzed them in a complementary manner. The closed-question
data consisted of attitude-scaled questions that ascertained the principals' use and application of the best-
interests concept. We recorded the responses to attitude questions on a five-point Likert scale, which asked
participants to check their level of agreement with various statements. We sought further exploration of use and
application of the best-interests principle through open-ended questions.
We subjected the quantitative data from the 11 closed attitudinal ques- tions to descriptive statistical analysis to
identify central categories. We provide simple percentages of responses with means and standard deviations,
but note the uneven cell sizes and response rate due to variance in completed mail-out and on-line versions of
the survey. We subjected the qualitative data from the open-ended questions to thematic analysis. We grouped
the results of the analyses of qualitative data and presented them according to emergent themes. Responses to
open-ended questions were coded according to the dominant recurring themes in the responses (MacMillan
&Schumacher, 2006). Codes were then combined into categories, and categories into patterns or concepts
(Lichtman, 2010). Analysis of open-ended responses provided rich descriptive data for the study.
The demographic data for the study included six categories: age, gender, province, years of professional
experience, years of experience as a princi- pal, and formal ethical training (See Table 1).
The participating principals fitted into four age-range categories; most (81%) belonged to the 41-60 age group.
Gender representation showed a slight prevalence of male principals. Two thirds of the respondents had 21 or
more years as a professional educator, and most had held administrative positions for up to 10 years.
More than three quarters of the participants held master's and a few had doctoral degrees. More than half
reported some formal training in ethics, which consisted of university-level courses in ethics or ethical
23 October 2014 Page 10 of 26 ProQuestleadership as well as board or school professional development activities (or a combination of both).
Research Findings: Principals' Perceptions of the Best-Interests Principle
The findings were grouped into the following categories: definitions and significance of the best-interests
principle; familiarity, use, and efficacy of the best-interests principle; preference for resolving best interests
individually or communally; and ethical paradigm preferences in resolving best-interests dilemmas.
Definition and Description of the Best-Interests Concept
Given the view in the literature that educational leaders frequently justify their actions as in the best interests of
children, we were interested in their definitions and perceptions of the significance of the best-interests principle.
In this section we discuss data from the following open-ended questions: How do you prefer to define "in the
best interests of the student(s)"? How would you explain "in the best interests of the student(s)" to a new staff
member? We were not expecting different responses to these questions, but rather chose to ask the descriptive
and definitional question in two ways.
Analyses of the data revealed that the notion of the best interests of the student(s) was broadly conceptualized
and defined in three major categories of thought: best interests as core good, best interests as good pedagogy,
and best interests as comprehensive good. Most respondents identified with a definition of best interests as a
core good. The best interests of students were regularly described as the core or center of decision-making and
the heart of educators' work. One respondent noted, "I would ask staff members to always remember why we
teach-to educate students. They are our priority." It was evident that the respondents mitigated decisions of best
interests by placing the students at the heart of decision-making, or as one respondent articulated, "We need to
see to their needs ahead of our own." Prevalently, respondents defined best interests as the why of their work
and why they entered teaching. Respondents identified an ethical duty and responsibility toward providing
students with the best possible care and attention including decisions on their behalf. This sense of service
responsibility prevailed that: "Students are our client and we have a responsibility to our students" and that an
agreed central purpose of education, best interests, should be "to serve students." Finally, respondents defined
best interests as the best outcome or as a positive benefit. Decision-making in this manner was depicted as
those decisions that led to students' development, advancement, and growth. One comment encapsulates this
point: "What the phrase [best interest] means to me is that decisions are made from the perspective of providing
the best possible outcome for that child."
When describing best interests as good pedagogy, principals used concepts and phrases like learning,
achievement, learning environment, and pedagogy. The best-interests principle was described as a means to
an end. In the view of some respondents, the central purpose or paramount reason for education was students'
learning as indicated in the following responses: "Our central purpose is student learning. I prefer to define 'best
interests' in the context of good pedagogy," and "I would explain it by saying that the paramount reason we are
in business is to advance student learning. If the decision advances student learning, then it is in the best
interest of the student." Decisions of best interests were identified by the respondents as those that "supported]
student learning [and] achievement in a safe and caring learning environment" or enabled students to "flourish
in an environment that is safe and productive to learning." In addition, the respondents defined decisions of best
interests as "interests that [led] to growth through learning opportunities" and higher achievement."
Finally, respondents defined best interests as a comprehensive good, wherein decision processes acknowledge
the complexity of educating students and recognize their multi-faceted lives. Respondents indicated that the
"best interests of the students has to embrace academic, social, emotional, spiritual and intellectual criteria [and
as such] the entire student has to be safeguarded." This way of thinking extended interests beyond narrow
interpretations. Whereas others might have depicted student learning or good pedagogy as the center, these
respondents envisaged a larger holistic context for the definition of best interests such that decisions were best
considered when "all the needs, dimensions and variables of student life" are accounted for.
As might have been expected, in defining best interests, the respondents identified three types of influences
23 October 2014 Page 11 of 26 ProQuestthat regulated, affected, and in some cases mitigated decisions in the best interests of student(s): stakeholders'
influence, contextual considerations, and relational aspects. Respondents' definitions of best interests were
mitigated by a sense that all of those involved in a decision, the stakeholders, should be considered.
Furthermore, decisions of best interest needed to consider the multiple stakeholders' needs, present and future.
At the same time, it was indicated that sometimes it might be necessary to override the influence of some
stakeholders in order not to jeopardize the best interests of the student(s). Respondents identified a range of
contextual considerations based on the availability and breadth of information about the situation. For example,
one participant noted that the information one has regarding a student's situation must come into play for each
decision made: "In the best interest of the student is a phrase used by people who believe that their decisions
and actions can affect the lives of the student(s) in their care ... Decisions are based on information: the better
the information the better the decision and how it will affect people." Finally, respondents indicated that
decisions of best interest needed to consider relational aspects together with the importance and significance of
attending to relationships among students and staff. One respondent wrote that best-interests decisions were
best made in the context of getting to know student(s) on a "personal level" and to "understand who they are as
people." The implication was that determinations of best interests are predicated on fostering honest, respectful,
and open relationships. Respondents also noted that open and positive communication and dialogue were
considered essential to the actualization of best interests. This raises the question of individual and collective
perspectives on the best interests of the students, which we address below.
Familiarity, General Use, and Perceived Efficacy
Participants were asked to describe the familiarity, general use, and perceived efficacy of the in the best
interests of the student(s) principle. Their responses are outlined in Table 2.
Most of the respondents indicated either strong agreement or agreement with the familiarity of the best-interests
principle and claimed to use the concept routinely in their administrative decision-making. Eighty-six percent of
the respondents strongly agreed or agreed that the best-interests principle was an efficacious means of
resolving ethical challenges in administrative decision-making. The efficacy of the best-interests principle
registered a higher percentage of neutral responses (13%) than that of familiarity and use.
The use of the best-interests principle, further explored in the open-ended questions, revealed five broad
circumstances where in-school administrators used best interests as a means of decision-making: discipline
matters, pedagogical considerations, human resources, special education, and safety. Most frequently,
respondents identified discipline as a time when the notion of best interests was used to justify a decision. The
discipline cases provided by the respondents ranged from alternate options to suspension and expulsion,
safety, and the general enforcement of school rules and expectations. Examples of the cases discussed and
elaborated on included giving a student coaching and extra chances based on his or her background and recent
23 October 2014 Page 12 of 26 ProQuestbehavior, shortening suspensions given individual circumstances even if in conflict with policy, contravening the
practice of contacting parents if family dynamics did not support contact, providing in-school suspensions when
home life was unsafe or when overriding the wishes of teachers. However, even more compelling than the
particulars of the discipline cases was the emergence of three themes discussed above: the need to recognize
the individual student, the influence of stakeholders, and the need to attend to matters such as relationship-
building and dialogue.
Pedagogical instances like learning, programming, or scheduling were also frequently mentioned as deliberative
times when the concept of best interests was used to justify a decision. Some of the pedagogical cases
discussed and elaborated on included learning adaptations for individual needs' student placement, retention,
and advancement; and programming suited to learning and students. Instances of using the best interests to
justify a decision in areas of human resources and staffing showed that the principle had become the mitigating
factor in resolving matters such as possible staffing reassignments, hiring or termination of teaching and support
staff, and staff disciplinary or supervisory matters. As one respondent wrote, "I had to decide whether I could
sacrifice 2.5 teacher associate positions so I could keep a full-time teacher. My decision was made upon the
best interests of the students." In terms of special education, respondents identified the philosophy and nature
of inclusion and the practical means of integration as most common incidences when a best-interests
justification was used. Least frequent was the mention of the best-interests principle in potential unsafe or
supervisory practices where the resolution of the matter was mired in conflict between or among staff, parents,
students, or community expectations of safety.
Preference to Resolving Best-Interests Dilemmas: Individual or Collective
In-school administrators were asked to indicate a preference for resolving matters of best interests as either
upholding the individual (student) or the communal (students) interests. Their responses are outlined in Table 3.
Most participating school administrators (83%) strongly agreed that the optimal test of a difficult ethical situation
was whether the decision supported the best interests of all students. On the other hand, a more moderate
percentage of principals (64%) agreed that the optimal test of a difficult situation was whether the decision
supported the best interests of the individual student.
Participants' verbatim responses added more clarity on the collective or individual use of the best-interests
principle as an optimal test. Despite the widespread articulation that most students' interests should take
precedence, many respondents acknowledged the recognition of individual students' needs. Of course, this
course of inquiry was highly dependent on situations imagined or experienced by the respondents. However,
most of the respondents identified the need for a balanced approach in weighing the interests of the collective
student body and each individual student: "We always need to do what is in the best interest of individual
students; however, we must be aware of the message decisions send for the collective learning community we
23 October 2014 Page 13 of 26 ProQuestserve." With this comes the difficulty of being multifocused or "keeping in mind the student's welfare (physical,
intellectual, emotional), including the balancing of individual and common needs when making decisions."
Instrumental in this test was the relation of the best-interests-of-students principle with the notions of fairness
and equality, or as one principal phrased it, "Fair is not equal; fair is giving everyone what they need, but yet
what is best for each child."
Ethical Paradigm Preference in Resolving Best-Interests Dilemmas
In order to assess how educational leaders make determinations in the best interest of the student(s) and what
factors influenced those decisions, respondents were asked to identify their attitude to five ethical paradigms
influencing their decisions: justice, care, critique, profession, and community. Participating principals' responses
to survey questions and the corresponding ethical paradigms are shown in Table 4.
Analysis of attitudinal questions revealed that respondents rated the ethic of care highly among the ethical
paradigms. The ethic of critique and professional code of ethics received a similar rating behind the ethic of
care, and the ethics of justice and community received lower rankings among the ethical paradigms.
Respondents were not given extended definitions of these ethical paradigms, but rather responded to nominal,
descriptive statements. As such, we offer these findings only as possible signals of respondents' dispositions
toward each ethical paradigm.
The qualitative data provided somewhat different results, whereas frequency of mention and significance
assigned by respondents to each ethic confirmed a ranked preference ranging from the ethic of care, ethic of
critique, ethic of profession, ethic of community, and ethic of justice. Analysis of these data revealed that the
respondents had not envisaged best interests in discrete terms, but rather in a complex manner consisting of
multiple or mixed ethical paradigms. The high incidences of the ethic of care among the qualitative data were
comparable to the quantitative data results. Respondents repeatedly articulated an emphasis on relationships,
dialogue, and integrity of the student or stakeholder involved. In the words of one principal, "I need students to
23 October 2014 Page 14 of 26 ProQuesttrust that I will put them first. I need the teachers to trust I will support them. I need parents to know I will do
everything possible to provide the best for their children."
Similarly, ways of thinking consistent with the ethic of justice and critique also prevailed in the open-ended
responses. Verbatim statements elicited from the participants revealed that they made considerations of equity
and fairness, as well as giving attention to voice and social justice, in their deliberations and perceptions of best
interest. Minimal references were made to specific codes and responsibilities of in-school administrators within
specific provincial and district regions that guided best interests. Rather, analysis suggested a widespread
recognition or universal acceptance of general, philosophical standards of the profession and of educators in
general, that is, the purpose and heart of best interests were the student and students.
Whereas analysis of the quantitative data indicated that respondents ranked considerations of the ethic of
community low among other ethical considerations, analysis of the qualitative data revealed a higher and more
significant role for this ethic. A prevalent theme among respondents' data was attention to communal manners
of thinking and behaving consistent with ethic of community, communication, collaboration, dialogue, and
stakeholders' involvement. In regard to the ethic of community, we found that "best interest of the school
community" and "accountability to the school community" were common descriptors. Community served as a
catalyst for one principal's decisions: "In my community, there is always talk about decisions being made. Often
the blame is placed upon me. I however feel confident knowing I have made a decision in the best interest of
the students."
Further to the above, principals were asked to tell about specific examples of the practical application of the
notion of best interests of students. Several of the participating administrators described working with certain
initiatives in the best interests of students.
* We started a program for autistic students and decided to embrace an inclusive school model in delivering that
program. This was in the best interest of all students and so we moved to support and promote that model. It
was hard because we were asking staff to teach and organize in a way that was different from the norm.
* I have kept students from going to the adjacent lot owned and equipped by the Community's recreation
association during school time as there is not adequate supervision for these students while they are over there.
Our school board does not provide supervision off property-it's not a risk I am willing to take.
* During staffing I have assigned teaching duties to a teacher because he was the best qualified rather than
assign the course to a teacher who did not have the qualifications but wanted the course.
* Students were out at recess and one student got upset with another and punched the student, then removed
himself from the situation on his own accord. I decided not to follow through on a suspension for the student as
he had made a conscious decision to stop and get out of the situation. Teacher wanted me to suspend, but I felt
that the student would learn more by working the situation through and working with the student he had trouble
with.
* Students were assigned to work as a small group on a cooperative activity; one student really wanted to work
alone and had shown us that it was the best way for him to stay on task and produce his best work. He was
allowed to work alone and the other two students worked as a pair.
Through analysis of these findings, we have glimpsed into and worked to grasp the array of situations entailed
in the work of principals who indirectly and directly wonder what might be in the best interests of the students
under their care. How might we understand the interpretations and use that principals seem to make of the
notion of the best interests of students?
Discussion: Best-Interests Model and the Educational Leader
As observed in the findings, the participating Canadian in-school administrators conceived the principle in best
interests of the student(s) in ways somewhat consistent with the professional ethic and best interests models in
the literature. Yet their conception of best interests moved beyond the current models and literature to include
best interests as moral imperative. They reaffirmed the multidimensional ethical framework (ethics of justice,
23 October 2014 Page 15 of 26 ProQuestcare, critique, and profession) and placed emphasis on an emerging role of the ethic of community.
Moral Imperative: Best Interests of Student(s)
This study affirmed the importance of moral and ethical considerations in educational administration. The
findings support Foster's (1986) observation that each administrative decision carries with it a restructuring of
human life and, therefore, administration at its heart is the resolution of moral dilemmas. Furthermore, as
Stefkovich (2006) contends, "it is incumbent on school leaders to make ethical decisions that truly reflect the
needs of the students and not their own self-interests ... it requires a great deal of self-reflection, open-
mindedness, and an understanding that making ethically sound decisions profoundly influences others' lives" (p.
21). These authors, with Hodgkinson (1991), suggest that there is a moral art to educational leadership that
differentiates or even distinguishes the role from more mechanical, rational-technical, and managerial roles. The
stewardship of vulnerable children and the entrustment of parents, state, and community obligate educational
leaders to high standards of care and moral deliberation.
Participants affirmed the "contested nature of educational problem-solving" (Begley &Zaretsky, 2004, p. 653)
and revealed a dichotomy of conceiving best interests. Whereas defining best interests as the ethical foundation
for educational decision-making was evident, the data also suggest that interests were simultaneously narrowly
and broadly defined such as in pedagogical and comprehensive-good definitions.
Respondents conveyed the effect of the clash of interests on educational decision-making by identifying the
possible limitations. They concurred that although identifying best interests was a complicated and difficult task,
adherence to the principle was still just and right despite those challenges. As Vojak (2003) notes, even if one
acknowledges that best interests are not always discernible, it should not keep one from striving toward best
interests as an ideal. In this respect the data indicate that the best-interests principle plays a significant role in
directing the reasoning, judgment, and deliberation of in-school administrators.
This conception of the best-interests principle echoes the prevalent argument in the literature that the principle
of best interests is an ideal. The respondents in this study consistently identified in their definitions that the
principle of best interests was the guiding purpose of educational administration and as such the core good of
sound decision-making. In addition, social and moral duties that underpin the jurisprudential construct of
responsibility were also evident in the data. As Kopelman (1997) noted, "best interests standard makes little
sense unless it is understood not as an absolute duty, but as a prima facie duty or an ideal that should guide
choices" (p. 277). As an ideal construct, the best interests of students may be seen as a lighthouse giving us
perspective and helping us steer or navigate our best course on behalf of students. Research on how principals
respond when confronted with ethical dilemmas suggests that the best interests of students figure prominently
as a meta-organizer and ultimate influence on their decision-making (Stefkovich &Begley, 2007).
Multidimensional Ethical Framework
The current literature continues to emphasize the significance of the ethics of justice, care, critique, and
profession for real-life ethical dilemmas in leadership practices of in-school administrators (Langlois &Lapointe,
2007; Shapiro &Stefkovich, 2011). The first three ethics have been frequently discussed in the field of
educational leadership. Starratt (2003) argued that each ethic needs the strong connections embedded in the
other; the ethic of justice needs profound commitment to the dignity of the individual person and the profound
social analysis of the ethic of critique; the ethic of care needs the larger attention to social order and fairness;
and the ethic of critique requires an ethic of care if it is to avoid the cynical and depressing ruminations of the
habitual malcontent.
This study reinforced the interconnectedness of the three ethics in the ethical decision-making of in-school
administrators. Incidences of thinking consistent with the three ethics were prevalent in the data. In many cases,
the responses of the in-school administrators exhibited the complexity and layering of ethical
interconnectedness. In-school administrators tended to balance the students' right to learning (ethic of justice),
the comprehensive needs of the student (ethic of care), students' self-interests (ethic of justice/ care), and the
23 October 2014 Page 16 of 26 ProQuesteffect on current/future student relationships (ethic of critique). This finding may be attributed to the years of
experience, as most of the respondents in this study had been in administrative positions for six or more years,
and almost a quarter had 11 or more years of experience. The interconnectedness of ethics allows for fuller
expression of ethical leadership and is linked to the number of years of experience gained as a principal;
experience is a key factor in the development of a professional ethic that is reflexive rather than procedural
(Langlois &Lapointe, 2007).
Recently, Shapiro and Stefkovich (2011) reinforced the existence of the fourth ethic, that of profession, in a
stand-alone form. Their concept of professional ethics as an ethical paradigm includes ethical principles and
codes of ethics embodied in the ethic of justice, as well as professional judgment and decision-making. They
recognize professional ethics as a dynamic process requiring administrators to develop their own personal and
professional codes. Shapiro and Stefkovich believe that educational leaders should be given the opportunity to
take the time to develop their own personal codes of ethic based on life stories and critical incidents, and create
their professional codes based on the experiences and expectations of their working lives as well as a
consideration of their personal codes. This sense of self as an administrator and its connection to best interests
was evident in our study. As one respondent wrote, best interests are best defined and achieved by "putting
one's own biases, prejudices and preconceptions aside and dealing with the student(s) as an individual-a
student-centered approach where the dignity of the individual must remain intact-where the adult must act in a
reasonable way and with common sense." However, minimal references were made to specific professional
codes and responsibilities in various provincial and district jurisdictions that guided best interests; instead, it was
the universal standards of the profession-that students are the purpose and heart of best interests-that guided
principals' work.
This study emphasized the significance of the ethic of community in a conception of best interests. Shapiro and
Stefkovich (2001b, 2011) and Stefkovich (2006) place the ethic of community in the larger context of the
multidimensional ethical framework and their proposed professional ethic, whereas Furman (2004) advocates
for a wholly distinct and separate conception. Furman's approach differs from those of scholars who view
community as an entity and/or see it in relation to the individual and thus join it with another paradigm (Beck,
1994; Purpel, 2004; Sergiovanni, 1992; Shapiro &Stefkovich, 2011). In Furman's depiction of the ethic of
community, emphasis is placed on the communal and methodological modes of thinking including those of
communication, collaboration, dialogue, and stakeholders' involvement.
The significance of stakeholders' involvement was denoted by the respondents as one of the three major
influences on decisions of best interests, whereas the importance of communication, dialogue, and relationship-
building was evident among all three broad categories of thought defining best interests. In addition, the notion
of a community of educators with a common vision pointed to the collective nature of best interests. The data
echo the African proverb that it takes a village to raise a child and thus views the child not as a product of
individual effort, but of collective interaction and intervention. However, Noddings (2002) issued a warning that
communities can act like bloated individuals. To offset this possibility of bloatedness or groupthink, Noddings
suggested that individuals acquire the ability to accept the ideas and commitments of the community while
resisting community pressures for conformity or orthodoxy. To accomplish this vision, one must have self-
knowledge, but also a knowledge of others that is gained through ongoing communication (Stefkovich, 2006).
However, despite the occurrence of communication, collaboration, dialogue, and stakeholders' involvement in
the data, incidences of expressions of the ethic of community occurred in relation to other ethical positions and
not in isolation. That is, the ethic of community was not conceived discretely, but in unison with other ethical
paradigms of justice, care, critique, and profession. The inclusion of the ethic of community among the other
ethics in the data extends the interconnectedness and complexity of ethical decision-making (Shapiro
&Stefkovich, 2011; Starratt, 2003; Stefkovich, 2006).
23 October 2014 Page 17 of 26 ProQuestAs shown in Figure 1, the best-interests principle was viewed by the principals as the center or heart of their
work (Bishop-Yong, 2010). The interconnectedness of the four ethics of care, justice, critique, and profession
included communal practices of communication, dialogue, collaboration, and stakeholders' involvement to bear
on decisions of best interests. However, this model must be interpreted in conjunction with the discussion of
individual versus collective and subjective versus objective interpretations of best interests.
Best-Interests Dichotomies
Conceptualizing the ethical interpretations of the best-interests principle is premised on the relational nature of
interests. As such, two central dichotomies emerge in interpretations of the best-interests principle in the ethical
literature, and it forms a matrix of best interests: individual versus collective and subjective versus objective (see
Figure 2). Other ways of expressing this dichotomy would be "ad hoc versus criteria-based" decisions or "act
versus rule" decisions. Walker (1998b) suggested that "where the subjective and objective elaborations,
sensitivities, interpretations, and applications meet" (p. 323), we will see the best interest of children and child.
Data analysis revealed a central position of in-school administrators vis àvis best interests on the matrix, where
in the light of legislation, public policy, and ethics, they have to choose an interest to uphold-the individual
(student) or the communal (students) and a methodology of deciding-subjective (case by case) or objective
(criteria based).
The matrix represents the arguments of several theorists on best interests such as Smith (1998), Capron
(1982), Walker (1998a) and Shapiro and Stefkovich (2002b) along the intersecting dichotomies. Smith, like the
judiciary, was concerned with the child in his critique of best interests per the educational leader. According to
Smith, there may be "no singular right, good, or virtuous pattern for all children," yet there may be a singularly
right response for the single child and what fundamentally determines the measure of help given the child is the
moral agency of "people [who] are in better positions relative to particular children than others" (p. 309).
Similarly, Shapiro and Stefkovich and Stefkovich (2006) centered their research on assisting those in "better
23 October 2014 Page 18 of 26 ProQuestpositions"-in-school administrators-to make ethical decisions in the best interests of the student. The underlying
assumpFi tion is that if the individual is treated with fairness, justice, and caring, then a strong message is sent
to all students that they will be afforded justice and caring and that they should treat others similarly
(Stefkovich). However, unlike Smith's assessment, Shapiro and Stefkovich appeared to hold the position of
whose interests, individual or collective, in a balance. Dworkin (1982) identified that the struggle for balancing
the interests of the individual and the communal lies in terms of not only value conflicts, but also time conflicts.
Writing about political representatives, he suggests that they are asked to balance the interests and desires of
some against those of others and may have to consider the interests of current generations against the needs
or interests of future generations. Once again, the nature of interests is relational.
In regard to individualistic notions of the best interest of a child or student, Smith (1998) advocated a singularly
subjective standard. Shapiro and Stefkovich's (2001b, 2005) models conversely advance a blended approach
by proposing a subjective, case-by-case analysis and an objective assessment of multidimensional ethical
paradigms and jurisprudential concepts. Capron (1982) identified the subjective and objective tension inherent
in instances of child-custody disputes and identified that the judiciary and related doctrine "seems to rest on an
'objective' standard of what a reasonable person would find appropriate for the ordinary child" (p. 126). In
application, Capron noted that this standard may amount to a highly subjective decision, but only subjective in
the sense that it reflects the values and beliefs of the judiciary, not those of its individual wards. This values
tension of the individual is reflected in Shapiro and Stefkovich's (2001b) and Frick's (2006) work on the conflicts
of personal and professional codes of ethics and their effect on mediating decisions for the best interest of the
student. Walker (1998b) echoes the tension between subjective and objective determinations of best interest in
his writings on best interests. Although he acknowledges the limited influence of subjective perspectives on
decisions of best interests, he insists on reserving the capacity for "community, parents and professional
magistrates to adjudicate these perspectives by independent and external criteria when conflicts arise." Walker
not only surmises the complexity and relational nature of objectivity and collectivism, but also hints at the
process that influences position on the matrix.
The views of the participating principals were premised on a balanced resolution of best interests using both a
subjective and an objective consideration. Among the best interests conceptualizations-the definitions, use,
influence factors, and how best-interests decisions were made-both objective and subjective considerations
were evident in respondents' thinking. Despite the occurrence of objective criteria such as pedagogical and
23 October 2014 Page 19 of 26 ProQuestcomprehensive considerations (academic, social, behavioral, emotional, spiritual, and intellectual) in defining
best interests, subjective considerations such as stakeholders' influence, contextual considerations, and
relational aspects influenced the position of this study on the matrix.
Despite a stronger preference in the quantitative data to consider the needs of all students rather than the
individual student, analysis of the qualitative data revealed a slight preference for considering the needs of the
individual. Respondents identified a range of contextual considerations including situational factors, weighing
the interests of the greater good and the individual student, as well as recognizing a balance therein. In matters
of discipline and special education, analysis revealed respondents' strong preference for recognizing individual
needs. In matters of human resources, analysis revealed a strong preference for considering the needs of all
students or communal needs. In pedagogical and safety matters, analysis revealed an equitable consideration
of individual and communal needs. In addition, the respondents' emphasis on respect, relationships, voice, and
dialogue in resolving matters of best interest articulated a tension between exclusively defining best interests in
either individual or collective terms. Balancing the notion of the ethical person (Starratt, 1994) with conceptions
of community (Furman, 2004) means balancing self-interests with the interests of students and other
stakeholders and implies reconciling the purposes of personal and professional codes and of education itself.
The principals' responses reported here exemplify this balancing effort.
The results of the study support Gathercoal's (1991) metaphor that "having your cake and eating it too requires
the ingredients of law, education, and ethics, mixed and stirred judiciously with firsthand experience and baked
at a public school setting until it rises to the occasion" (p. 122). The complexity of the context in which outcomes
and decisions of best interests of children are determined by the principals and leaders was articulated as the
need to balance the two intersecting dichotomies on the matrix. These findings lend hope to the creation of
more effective educative communities among in-school administrators (Walker, 1995).
Concluding Remarks
In the changing and challenging operational environment in which schools now operate, "it is not surprising that
educational leaders are often faced with ethical dilemmas in the course of their daily work as they endeavor to
make complex decisions in the best interests of both staff and students" (Cranston et al., 2006, p. 106). The
best interests models such as ethic of profession (Shapiro &Stefkovich, 2001) and a model for promoting a
student's best interests (Stefkovich, 2006) responded to their desire to make sense of a much used, yet
amorphous concept. Stefkovich (2006) identified the pressing need for a codified approach to best interests as
follows.
Understanding that adults possess a great deal of power in determining students' best interests and realizing
how easy it is to ignore the voices of those who literally have the most to lose, it is incumbent upon school
leaders to make ethical decisions that truly reflect the needs of students and not their own adult self-interest, (p.
21)
School principals as formal school leaders are positioned to function as mediators and animators of many
competing and complementary values and interests on behalf of various educational constituents (Walker,
1998a). In their work, the best-interests principle becomes a widely used ethical, legal, and social basis for
making policy and decisions involving children (Kopelman, 1997; Walker, 1995). In this article, we aspire to
provoke educators to engage in further conversations about the best interests of students and provide an
overview of a recent study of the concept as it is understood and used by Canadian school principals. We
discuss the moral nature of educational leadership through a multidimensional ethical framework that comprises
ethics of justice, care, critique, community, and profession. The research reported is intended to examine the
best-interests principle as commonly used and understood in Canadian in-school administrative practice. This
approach results in the presentation of a pluralistic and quasi-consensual articulation of the best interests of
students. We suggest that each of the ethical paradigms presented here will yield unique and valuable
perspectives beyond those offered by our respondents.
23 October 2014 Page 20 of 26 ProQuestForemost in this study is the affirmation of the constructs of the professional ethic and best-interests models
such as the significance of the multi-ethical paradigms and jurisprudential constructs of responsibility, respect,
and rights in educational administrative decision-making. The findings suggest that the respondents have not
envisaged best interests in discrete terms, but rather in a complex manner consisting of multiple or mixed
ethical paradigms. Based on their perspectives, a model of professional ethics and best interests depicts a
balanced use of the ethical paradigms of care, critique, and justice with the intertwined aspects of the ethic of
community, namely, communication, dialogue, collaboration, and stakeholders' involvement. The results of this
study place in-school administrators vis àvis best interests in the center of the matrix on the intersection
between the dichotomies of individual and communal and subjective and objective.
In conclusion, we posit that continued research into the best practices in ethical decision-making pedagogy and
the thoughtful and thorough examination of ideations that help administrators mediate difficult choices in the
best interests of students would serve to augment the findings of this study. Instrumental in such attempts would
be an extensive examination to understand the societal factors and the educational context in which Canadian
in-school administrators make decisions in the best interests of children, which could be then compared with
contexts in other countries. As education is a provincial responsibility in Canada and systems of education in
provinces and territories differ and are unique in some regard, we suggest that further inquiry to uncover the
effect of educational policies and cultural aspects of schooling in various jurisdictions is necessary.
Furthermore, we emphasize the need for continued research in the area of multiple ethical paradigms, ethical
leadership, and ethical decision-making" among in-school administrators and encourage school leaders to apply
the principle of the best interests of the child by bringing into consideration the commonly taken-for-granted
jurisprudential and ethical meanings and interpretations that are perhaps over-embedded and underconsidered
in the cliché-oriented notion of the best interests of the child.
Acknowledgment
This work was supported by a grant from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada.
References
References
Apple, M.W. (1988). Teachers and texts: A political economy of class and gender relations in education. New
York: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Apple, M.W. (2001). Educating the "right" way: Markets, standards, God, and inequality. New York: Routledge
Falmer.
Apple, M.W. (2003). The State and the Politics of Knowledge. New York: Routledge Falmer.
Bailey, S. (2006). Decision making in acute care: A practical framework supporting the 'best interests' principle.
Nursing Ethics, 13,284-291.
Beck, L.G. (1994). Reclaiming educational administration as a caring profession. New York: Teachers College
Press.
Beckner, W. (2004). Ethics for educational leaders. Boston, MA: Pearson.
Begley, P.T. (2006). Self-knowledge, capacity and sensitivity: Prerequisites to authentic leadership by school
principals. Journal of Educational Administration, 44, 570-589.
Begley, P.T. (Ed.). (1999). Values and educational leadership. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
Begley, P.T., &Zaretsky, L. (2004). Democratic school leadership in Canada's public school systems:
Professional value and social ethic. Journal of Educational Administration, 42, 640655.
Bishop-Yong, N. (2010). The best interests principle in administrative practice: Canadian in-school
administrators' perceptions, definitions and use of the best interests principle. Unpublished master's thesis.
University of Saskatchewan.
Bitensky, S. (1992). Theoretical foundations for a fight to education under the U.S. Constitution: A beginning to
the end of the national education crisis. Northwestern University Law Review 86, 550-642.
23 October 2014 Page 21 of 26 ProQuestBush, T. (1998). The National Professional Qualification for Headship: The key to effective school leadership?
School Leadership and Management, 18, 321-334.
Bush, T. (2008). From management to leadership: Semantic or meaningful change? Educational Management,
Administration and Leadership, 36, 271-288.
Bush, T. (2011). Theories of educational leadership and management (4th ed.). London: Sage.
Campbell, E. (1999). Ethical school leadership: Problems of an elusive role. In P. Begley (Ed.), Values and
educational leadership (pp. 151-163). Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
Capron, A.M. (1982). The competence of children as self-deciders in biomedical interventions. In W. Gaylin &R.
Macklin (Eds.), Who speaks for the child: The problems of proxy consent (pp. 57-114). New York: Plenum
Press.
Clarke, P.T., Heavin, H., &Walker, K.D. (2010). Racist parenting and the best interests of the child: A legal and
ethical analysis. Canadian Journal of Educational Administration and Policy, 109,1-47.
Cranston, N., Ehrich, L. C., &Kimber, M. (2006). Ethical dilemmas: The "bread and butter" of educational
leaders' lives, journal of Educational Administration, 44,106-121.
Cuban, L. (1998). The managerial imperative and the practice of leadership in schools. Albany, NY: SUNY
Press.
Denig, S.J., &Quinn, T. (2001). Ethical dilemmas for school administrators. The High School journal, 84(4), 43-
50.
Department of Justice Canada. (2004). Fact sheet Section 43 of the Criminal Code Corporal Punishment: The
Canadian Foundation for Children, Youth and the Law v. The Attorney General of Canada. Available:
http://canada.justice.gc.ca/en/news/fs/2004/doc_31114.html
Donlevy, Kv &Walker, K. (2011). Working through ethics in education and leadership. Rotterdam, Netherlands:
Sense Publications.
Duignan, P., &Bhindi, N. (1997). Authenticity in leadership: an emerging perspective, journal of Educational
Administration, 35,195-209.
Dworkin, G. (1982). Consent, representation and proxy consent. In W. Gaylin &R. Macklin (Eds.), Who speaks
for the child: The problems of proxy consent (pp. 191-208). New York: Plenum Press.
Evers, C., &Lakomski, G. (1990). Knowing educational administration: Contemporary methodological
controversies in educational administration research. Oxford, UK: Pergamon Press.
Foster, W. (1986). Paradigms and promises: New approaches to educational administration. Buffalo, NY:
Prometheus Books.
Foucault, M. (1983). On the genealogy of ethics: an overview of work in progress. In H. L. Dreyfus &P. Rabinow
(Eds.), Michel Foucault: Beyond structuralism and hermeneutics (2nd ed., pp. 229-252). Chicago, IL: University
of Chicago Press.
Freire, P. (1970). Pedagogy of the oppressed (M.B. Ramos, Trans.). New York: Continuum.
Frick, W. (2006). An empirical investigation of secondary principals' perspectives on "the best interests of the
students" as a viable professional ethic for educational leadership. Unpublished doctoral dissertation,
Pennsylvania State University.
Furman, G.C. (2004). The ethic of community. Journal of Educational Administration, 42,215-235.
Gathercoal, F. (1991). judicious discipline (2nd ed.). Davis, CA: Caddo Gap Press.
Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Giroux, H.A. (1994). Educational leadership and school administrators: Rethinking the meaning of democratic
public culture. In T. Mulkeen, N.H. Cambron-McCabe &B. Anderson (Eds.), Democratic leadership: The
changing context of administrative preparation (pp. 31-47). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Greenfield, W. (2004). Moral leadership in schools, journal of Educational Administration, 42, 174-196.
Hallinger, P. (2003). Reshaping the landscape of school leadership: A global perspective. Lisse, Netherlands:
23 October 2014 Page 22 of 26 ProQuestSwets and Zeitlinger.
Hodgkinson, C. (1978). Towards a philosophy of administration. New York: St. Martin's Press.
Hodgkinson, C. (1991). Educational Leadership: the moral art. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
Hoyle, E., &Wallace, M. (2005). Educational leadership: Ambiguity, professionals, and managerialism. London:
Sage.
Johansson, O. (2004). A democratic, learning and communicative leadership. Journal of Educational
Administration, 42, 697-707.
Jonsen, A. (1968). Responsibility in modern religious ethics. Washington, DC: Corpus Books.
Katz, M.S., Noddings, Ν., &Strike, K. (Eds.). (1999). Justice and caring: The search for common ground in
education. New York: Teachers College Press.
Kimbrough, R.B. (1985). Current study for educational leader. Arlington, VA: American Association of School
Administrators.
Kopelman, L.M. (1997). The best-interests standard as a threshold, ideal, and standard of reasonableness.
Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 22, 271-289.
Langlois, L. (2004). Responding ethically: Complex decision-making by school district superintendents.
International Studies in Educational Administration and Management, 32(2), 78-93.
Langlois, L. (2008). Anatomie d'un leadership éthique. Quebec, QC: Université Laval.
Langlois, L., &Lapointe, C. (2007). Ethical leadership in Canadian school organizations: Tensions and
possibilities. Educational Management Administration &Leadership, 35, 247-260. doi: DOI:
10.1177/1741143207075391
Langlois, L., &Starratt, R. J. (2001). Identification of superintendent and school commissioners' ethical
perspective: A case study and overlapping ethical framework: data talking to the model. Paper presented at the
Conference on Ethics and Leadership, Charlotteville, VA.
Lichtman, M. (2010). Qualitative research in education: A user's guide. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
MacMillan, J.H., &Schumacher, S. (2006). Research in education: Evidence-based inquiry. Boston, MA:
Pearson.
Noddings, N. (1984). Feminine approach to ethics and moral education. Berkeley, CA: University of California
Press.
Noddings, N. (1999). Care, justice, and equity. In M.S. Katz, N. Noddings, &K.A. Strike (Eds.), Justice and
caring: The search for common ground in education (pp. 7-20). New York: Teachers College Press.
Noddings, N. (2002). Educating moral people: A caring alternative to character education. New York: Teachers
College Press.
Noddings, N. (Ed.). (2005). The challenge to care in schools: An alternative approach to education (2nd ed.).
New York: Teachers College Press.
Normore, A.H. (2004). Ethics and values in leadership preparation programs: Finding the north star in the dust
storm. Values and Ethics in Educational Administration, 2(2), 1-8.
Northouse, P.G. (2013). Leadership (6th ed.). London: Sage.
Purpel, D.E. (2004). Reflections on the moral and spiritual crisis in education. New York: Peter Lang.
Rebore, R.W. (2001). The ethics of educational leadership. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Merrill Prentice Hall.
Rucinski, A.D., &Bauch, P.A. (2006). Reflective, ethical, and moral constructs in educational leadership
preparation: Effects on graduates' practices. Journal ofEducational Administration, 44, 487-508.
Selznick, P. (1984). Leadership in administration: A sociological approach. San Francisco, CA: Harper Row.
Sergiovanni, T.J. (1992). Moral leadership: Getting to the heart of school improvement. San Francisco, CA:
Jossey-Bass.
Sernak, K. (1998). School leadership: Balancing power with caring. New York: Teachers College Press.
Shapiro, J. P. (2006). Ethical decision making in turbulent time: bridging theory with practice to prepare
23 October 2014 Page 23 of 26 ProQuestauthentic educational leaders. Values and Ethics in Educational Administration, 4(2), 1-8.
Shapiro, J.P., &Gross, S. (2008). Ethical leadership in turbulent times: (Re)Solving moral dilemmas. New York:
Erlbaum.
Shapiro, J.P., &Hassinger, R.E. (2007). Using case studies of ethical dilemmas for the development of moral
literacy: Towards educating for social justice. Journal of Educational Administration, 45, 451-470.
Shapiro, J.P., &Stefkovich, J.A. (2001a). Ethical leadership and decision making in education: Applying
theoretical perspectives to complex dilemmas. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Shapiro, J.P., &Stefkovich, J.A. (2001b). Response of the review of ethical leadership and decision making in
education. British Journal of Educational Psychology, 71,364.
Shapiro, J.P., &Stefkovich, J.A. (2005). Ethical leadership and decision making in education: Applying
theoretical perspectives to complex dilemmas (2nd ed.). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Shapiro, J.P., &Stefkovich, J.A. (Eds.). (2011). Ethical leadership and decision making in education: Applying
theoretical perspectives to complex dilemmas (3rd ed.). New York: Routledge.
Smith, S. (1998). A child's best interests: A commentary on "jurisprudential and ethical perspectives on the best
interests of children" by Keith Walker. Interchange, 29(3), 309-316.
Starratt, R.J. (1991). Building an ethical school: A theory for practice in educational leadership. Educational
Administration Quarterly, 27,185-202.
Starratt, R.J. (1994). Building an ethical school: A practical response to the moral crisis in schools. London:
Falmer Press.
Starratt, R.J. (2003). Centering educational administration: Cultivating meaning, community, responsibility.
Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Starratt, R.J. (2004). Ethical leadership. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Starratt, R.J. (2005). Responsible leadership. Educational Forum, 69(2), 124-133.
Starratt, R.J. (2010). Developing successful leadership. In B. Davies &M. Brundrett (Eds.), Studies in
educational leadership (vol. 11, pp. 27-37). Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer.
Stefkovich, J.A. (2006). Best interests of the student: Applying ethical constructs to legal cases in education.
Mahwah, NJ: Earlbaum.
Stefkovich, J.A., &Begley, P. (2007). Ethical school leadership: Defining the best interests of students.
Educational Management, Administration, &Leadership, 35, 205-224.
Stefkovich, J.A., &O'Brien, M. (2004). Best interests of the student: An ethical model. Journal of Educational
Administration, 42, 197-214.
Stefkovich, J.A., &Shapiro, J.P. (2003). Deconstructing communities: Educational leaders and their ethical
decision-making processes. In P. Begley &O. Johansson (Eds.), The ethical dimensions of school leadership
(pp. 89-106). Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer Academic.
Strike, K., Haller, E., &Soltis, J. (1988). The ethics of school administration. New York: Teachers College Press.
Tirri, K. (1999). Teachers' perceptions of moral dilemmas at school, journal of Mora! Education, 28(1), 31-47.
Tirri, K., &Husu, J. (2002). Care and responsibility in 'the best interest of the child': Relational voices of ethical
dilemmas in teaching. Teachers and Teaching: Theory and practice, 8(1), 65-80.
Vojak, C. (2003). Mozert v. Hawkins: A look at self-knowledge and the best interests of the child. Educational
Theory, 53,401-418.
Walker, K. (1991). Theory to practice: Ethics in policy research and development. In R. Reilly &C. Lautar (Eds.),
Policy research and development in Canadian education (pp. 73-99). Calgary, AB: University of Calgary Press.
Walker, K. (1995). A principled look at 'the best interests of the children'. Canadian School Executive, 15(5), 3-
8.
Walker, K. (1998a). Jurisprudential and ethical perspectives on "the best interests of children." interchange,
29(3), 287-308. doi: 10.1023/a:1007561315049
23 October 2014 Page 24 of 26 ProQuestWalker, K. (1998b). Response to Dr. Stephen Smith. Interchange, 29(3), 317-326.
Walker, K., &Donlevy, K. (2006). Reconsidering ethical relativism. Journal of School Leadership, 16, 216-239.
Walker, Κ., &Donlevy, K. (2009). The four ethical commitments in educational administration. Journal of
Educational Thought, 43,109-131.
Willower, D.J. (1999). Work on values in educational administration: some observations. Paper presented at the
annual meeting of the University Council for Educational Administration Center for the Study of Ethics and
Leadership, Charlottesville, VA.
AuthorAffiliation
Keith Walker
University of Saskatchewan
Benjamin Kutsyuruba
Queen's University
Nicola Bishop-Yong
Westmount Community School, Saskatoon
AuthorAffiliation
Keith Walker, Professor, University of Saskatchewan, (Department of Educational Administration &Johnson
Shoyama Graduate School of Public Policy), keith.walker@usask.ca
Benjamin Kutsyuruba, Assistant Professor, Queen's University, (Faculty of Education),
ben.kutsyuruba@queensu.ca
Nicola Bishop-Yong, Principal, Westmount Community School, (Saskatoon Public School Division),
bishopn@spsd.sk.ca
Subject: Studies; School principals; Educational leadership; Professional ethics; Decision making;
Location: Canada
Publication title: EAF Journal
Volume: 22
Issue: 2
Pages: 27-I
Number of pages: 35
Publication year: 2011
Publication date: 2011
Year: 2011
Publisher: Journal of Educational Administration and Foundations
Place of publication: Winnipeg
Country of publication: Canada
Publication subject: Education--School Organization And Administration
ISSN: 08313318
Source type: Scholarly Journals
Language of publication: English
Document type: Feature
23 October 2014 Page 25 of 26 ProQuestDocument feature: Tables Charts References
ProQuest document ID: 1353572711
Document URL: http://search.proquest.com/docview/1353572711?accountid=25704
Copyright: Copyright Journal of Educational Administration and Foundations 2011
Last updated: 2013-12-09
Database: ProQuest Education Journals
_______________________________________________________________
Contact ProQuest
Copyright 2014 ProQuest LLC. All rights reserved. - Terms and Conditions
23 October 2014 Page 26 of 26 ProQuest
Posting Komentar